R O M A N I A N REVIEW OF POLITICA L S C I E N C E S A N D I NTERNATIONAL RELATIONS VOL. II No. 2 2005 CONTENT POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY HENRIETA ªERBAN, Lucian Blaga and Richard Rorty. The Historical Being and the Ironist ................................................................................................... ANA BAZAC, The analysis of Popper on Marx’s Method. Some nonconformist remarks .............................................................................................................. RÃZVAN PANTELIMON, Rawls, Nozick y Pettit. Una visión comparativa de la teoría de la justicia ............................................................................................ 3 13 24 POLITICAL SOCIOLOGY LUIS RENÉ ORO TAPIA, Invocación de Max Weber al Soneto 102 de Shakespeare .................................................................................................. FRANCESCO GUIDA, Idea di nazione e questione delle nazionalità nel pensiero di Giuseppe Mazzini.......................................................................................... GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA, L’évolution de la classe politique roumaine au XXe siècle ..................................................................................................... RODICA IAMANDI, The cult of personality in Romania, during communism ... 35 43 54 64 ARGUMENTS AND POINTS OF VIEW LUCIAN JORA, The Representation of history as a conflict prevention strategy............................................................................................................... ROBERTA MORETTI, Culianu in Italia ................................................................ CARMEN BURCEA, L’insegnamento del romeno in Italia fra le due guerre mondiali ............................................................................................................. 81 88 99 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE .................................................................................... 109 BOOK REVIEWS................................................................................................... 121 THE REVIEW OF REVIEWS................................................................................ 127 Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 1–129, Bucharest, 2005. POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY LUCIAN BLAGA AND RICHARD RORTY. THE HISTORICAL BEING AND THE IRONIST HENRIETA ªERBAN The question to pose in this comparative approach of two philosophical concepts that at the first glance have nothing in common is the following: “Is ironism an awakening from ‘the infinite sleep where our being floats’”? And the entire study struggles to sustain a positive answer to this question. I consider that Blaga’s architectural complex is a celebration of ironism avant-la-lettre. The parallel between the historical being and the “ironist” has its importance in the very contemporary relevance as in the hope it brings about: life brings about the opportunity to be exposed to different vocabularies, to so interesting vocabularies (read “worlds”, “ideas”) as either Blaga’s or Rorty’s. Both their thought and lives speak volumes about ironism. Approaching the parallel between ironism and the historical being, one understands that the tragic nature of the historical being is therefore counter-balanced, in a very complex and tensioned way, by the chances to live authentically as a (liberal) ironist and as an inherently creative being. Lucian Blaga — a fugitive biography of a great being Lucian Blaga (1895–1961), the Romanian philosopher who had his debut as a poet, obtained his Ph.D. title in philosophy and biology in Vienna (1916–1920). He continued to be a “complete” writer all his life, a poet and a dramatist, a philosopher and a journalist.1 Meanwhile he was as well a professor2, a researcher3 and a librarian.4 He gets inscribed into this great intellectual tradition of connecting and reconnecting Romanian culture to the world as a press attaché and counselor in Warsaw, Prague and Berna (1926–1936), as a state vice-secretary at the Ministry of Foreign Affairs (1936–1938), delegate minister of Romania in Portugal (1938–1939). In 1935 Lucian Blaga is awarded by the Romanian Academy the Great C. Hamangiu Prize “for his dramatic and poetic work”. After the Vienna Diktate he lives at Sibiu, lectures for the Faculty of Letters and Philosophy of the University of Cluj (1946–1948), researches at the Cluj Institute of History and Philosophy (1949–1951) to become afterwards the chief-librarian, at the Library of the Romanian Academy, Cluj section (1951–1954) and then vice-director at the same institution until 1959, two years before his departure for eternity in his natal village, the place where, in the words of the poet, “eternity itself was born”. Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 3–12, Bucharest, 2005. 4 HENRIETA ªERBAN 2 Lucian Blaga published, as a philosopher, several volumes of articles, essays and studies. The first one was Culture and Conscience in 1922 and then many more followed: The Philosophy of Style (1924), The Original Phenomenon and The Faces of a Century (both in 1925), Colloured Windows and Daimonion (both in 1925) The Dogmatic Aeon (1931), The Luciferic Knowledge (1933), The Transcendent Censorship (1934), Horizon and Style, and The Mioritic Space (both in 1936), The Eulogy of the Romanian Village, and The Genesis of Metaphor and the Sense of Culture (1937), Art and Value (1939), Divine Differentials (1940), About the Magic Thinking (1941), Religion and Spirit, and Science and Creation (both in 1942), On the Philosophical Conscience (1947) Anthropological Aspects (1948), Romanian Thought in Transylvania in the 18th Century (1966), Horizons and Stages (1968), The Experiment and the Mathematical Spirit (1969), Sources (1972), The Historical Being (1977), the last five volumes being published post-mortem. Lucian Blaga’s philosophy — the “historical being” The concept of “historical being” that Lucian Blaga developed is an important part of a larger philosophical architecture. Lucian Blaga himself presents his system, about the totality of existence, in The Sketch of a Philosophical SelfRepresentation (1934).5 The main part of this architecture is composed of three trilogies. The first one is The Trilogy of Knowledge, consisting in The Dogmatic Aeon, The Luciferic Knowledge and The Transcendent Censorship. The second one is The Trilogy of Culture formed by Horizon and Style, The Mioritic Space and The Genesis of Metaphor and the Sense of Culture. The third part is The Trilogy of Values concerning matters of art and value, matters of the philosophy of biology and matters of pure metaphysics. As a philosopher, Blaga wanted to build a system of a symphonic character, like a “church with many cupolas”.6 Blaga’s philosophical construction, metaphysical in nature, is not erected on the basis of one sole idea, but it relies on several, completing and consonant ideas. Each idea grows on the meanings startled by the others and triggers new horizons of meaning and understanding. Culture, history and historicism, time and temporality, being and becoming of being are only a few of the pillars of his architectural philosophy. The human being is a historical being but not merely a historical being. When we tackle historicism at Blaga we are in fact construing a being in a process of becoming, overcoming past mysteries and preparing for the future ones. The Historical Being (Fiinþa istoricã) is the final work of Lucian Blaga, published in 1977, post-mortem. There the author’s intention was to prepare the philosophical architecture for a “historical knowledge”, and eventually, for the ”metaphysics of history”. In the final chapter of this work, Blaga pays attention to the metaphysical aspects of a philosophy of history. He says that the historicism of the human being is “conditioned” metaphysically, in the sense that the history of each human has the core of a justification and a foundation of the permanent creative state of the human being. While he was still working at The Trilogy of Values, in 1938, 3 LUCIAN BLAGA AND RICHARD RORTY 5 he gave a speech entitled “About historical plenitude”, where he capitalizes on the Kantian tradition in the philosophy of culture, and as well on the “philosophy of symbolic forms” of E. Cassirer. In the latter, Blaga finds a parallel to his “metaphorizing being” in Cassirer’s7 expression “symbolic being” for the human being. History is therefore interesting mainly in the ontological leaps and in the ontological mutation that occasions and captures in any act of symbolic creation. From this perspective, the history is the history of the creator of human creativity, which is also the very human nature. The mechanisms and processes of human action are at the same time mechanisms and processes of human creativity. It seems that while he was preoccupied by the aspects of style, while he was transforming his interest for the “stylistic matrix” into attention towards a more complex and flexible notion of “stylistic field”, he was also developing a general field of becoming interesting for its stylistic dimensions as for its diachronically developments. Blaga keeps the pace with the cultural philosophy of his times (present at Goethe, Nietzsche, Simmel, Riegl, Worringer, Frobenius, Spengler, Keyserling…). In complementing the stylistic dimension with the historical dimension of human creativity, Blaga wants to surprise and consider creativity in its becoming and to surprise therefore the “medium” for an actualization of the very humanity of the human being. To analyze the historicity of the human being is at Blaga to understand the dual inner structure of human being: an existence in the horizon of the given world in the view of conserving his or her being (a “paradisiac” ontological mode) and an existence in the horizon of mystery that is to be revealed (a “luciferic” ontological mode). The later retains the core of historical existence of the human being. And, at their turn the historical phenomena keep a stylistic stygmate that defines them. Blaga’s historical being is forbidden access to absolute. But this very limitation the human being is obtaining both relativity and creativity. Mystery becomes a determinate and, at the same time, central philosophical category at Blaga. The philosopher understands that mystery has an important role to play into the constitution of the human knowledge. He states: “The ‘mystery’ exists for us as an original, irreducible horizon of our existence. Under the pressure and operations of the process of knowledge, this mystery precipitates itself in a multitude of ‘varieties’, that, logically, are very much determinable precisely in their quality of mysteries. Here are several of these ‘varieties’”.8 As the author explains, there is first of all the mystery as initial horizon of the manner of existence specific to the human being. Then there is the variety of the mystery that is “signaled” to us through our senses, an opened mystery, through the very signs related to our empirical sensitivity. Here is also the variety of the “revealed” mystery, at the constructive level of our knowledge, at the imaginary level and at the level of the abstract visions of our knowledge. Blaga underlines: “This mystery, both imaginary and revealed can be opened again as such and submitted to a new ‘revelation’. The process is infinite”.9 This infinite process is the mark of the infinite creativity of the human being. Philosophical thinking is called to unveil precisely this particular characteristics of the manner of existing through creativity, characterizing the humans. 6 HENRIETA ªERBAN 4 “Philosophical thinking, through its buildings and its debris, through its delusions and disappointments that it does provoke to us all, through the suspicions and presentiments that it communicates to us, through the ever deeper inquiries that occasions and invites, will mean therefore for the human genre an unlimited surplus of lucidity, its different stages being equivalent to as many ‘awakenings’ from the infinite sleep where our being floats.”10 Richard Rorty — brief biography Richard Rorty was born on the 4th of October 1931 in New York City, he was educated at the University of Chicago and at Yale University and he spent his early career complementing his personal interests and beliefs with the Platonic search for truth. His doctoral dissertation, “The Concept of Potentiality”, and his first book, The Linguistic Turn (1956) were part of the tradition of analytic philosophy. Discovering the pragmatist John Dewey and the post-analytic philosophers such as W.V. Quine and Wilfrid Sellars, he became a pragmatist, generally holding that the worth of an idea should be measured by its usefulness or ability to cope with a given problem, not by its correspondence to some antecedent “Truth”. And Rorty takes this definition to its most extreme point. In his major opus, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979), Rorty uses Sellars, Kuhn and Wittgenstein arguing that epistemology, the study of knowledge, is in fact the product of the mistaken view that the mind is a glassy essence, of which the main function is to faithfully reproduce external reality. He attacks “universal” philosophical investigations, such as the Mind/Body Problem, by historicizing them and exposing their contingency. Rorty argues for hermeneutics, the explaining of texts by other texts, rather than the search for an ultimate interpretation that would be validated by a higher force. Rorty is as famous for his other main work, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, published in 1989. In it, Rorty abandons the analytic attempt and creates an alternative conceptual schema based on the belief that there is no “truth” higher than the human being’s ability to recreate herself, a view that has been adapted from Nietzsche. This book also marks his first attempt to consciously articulate a political vision consonant with his philosophy, the vision of a diverse community bound together by opposition to suffering, and not by abstract ideas such as “justice”, “common humanity”, etc. Rorty is one of the most widely-read and controversial contemporary philosophers. Over the past fifteen years Rorty has published voluminously, including three volumes of philosophical papers, Achieving Our Country, a political manifesto partly based on readings of Dewey and Walt Whitman, and Philosophy and Social Hope, a collection of essays for a general audience. Having held teaching positions at Wellesley College, Princeton University and the University of Virginia, Rorty is currently a professor of comparative literature at Stanford University. 5 LUCIAN BLAGA AND RICHARD RORTY Rorty’s “ironism” 7 Rorty’s ironism is a post-analytical notion created around a certain profile of an individual, an ironist. After Rorty’s definition an “ironist” is “someone who fulfills three conditions: (1) she has radical and continuing doubts about the final vocabulary she currently uses, because she has been impressed by other vocabularies, vocabularies taken as final by people or books she has encountered; (2) she realizes that argument phrased in her present vocabulary ca neither underwrite or dissolve these doubts; (3) insofar as she philosophizes about her situation, she does not think that her vocabulary is closer to reality than others, that is in touch with a power not herself. Ironists who are inclined to philosophize see choice between vocabularies made neither within a neutral and universal metavocabulary nor by an attempt to fight one’s way past appearances to the real, but simply by playing the new off against the old.”11 So an ironist enjoys creatively other vocabularies as a continuous inspiration to their own vocabulary, continuously “under construction”. An ironist is still a philosopher either by training or by orientation, but not an analytic philosopher and, more precisely, not a “metaphysician”, that is, not someone who considers that “any term in his vocabulary has as correspondent something of a real essence”. Both intellectual types have in common the desire to know, but this has different manifestations and outcomes, in the case of the ironist and in that of the metaphysician. For the ironist the desire to know is not oriented to a unique and final vocabulary in the detriment of the others. Blaga in the light of “Rortian” ideas/Rorty in the light of Blaga’s ideas As Angela Botez has pointed out, Blaga’s modernity stays in interdisciplinarity and in the method of “transfigured antinomy”, that is the dual manner of thinking, characteristic for the entire 20th century. Then, Blaga’s postmodernity relays on integrative concepts such as the mystery or the two types of knowledge (“paradisiacal” and “luciferic”).12 Blaga’s metaphysics opens an avenue towards ironism. As a relative and creative historical being, the human always hopes to reach the absolute, in other terms to become substituted to the Great Anonymous and always fails. In Rortian terms, the human being is always threatened by the illusion to possibly get to a final vocabulary clear, true and definitive for all, but hopefully, as an ironist, fails to give way to this illusion. I came to observe that Rorty underlines in fact the static aspect of the metaphysics its “conservatism”, its need for secure roots in a never changing reality. At Blaga there is a dynamic element in his metaphysics. Actually to explain this aspect we have to return to the two types of ontology in Blaga’s philosophy. These types are strongly interwoven. First, there is an existence in the horizon of the given world in the view of conserving his or her being (a 8 HENRIETA ªERBAN 6 “paradisiacal” ontological mode) and an existence in the horizon of mystery that is to be revealed (a “luciferical” ontological mode). The latter retains the core of historical existence of the human being and at the same time it explains the dynamics of a more ironist-like thirst for knowledge. Blaga was an ironist. He loved being exposed to different vocabularies, as a poet and a playwright and a journalist and as a fervent reader, as a librarian. It seems that Rorty said at a recent conference, or at least the latest issue of the American literary journal “Off course”, quotes him so: “Our culture has not only been carried upward by a bubbling fountain of puns and metaphors; it has been increasingly conscious of itself as resting on nothing more solid than such a geyser.” And Blaga is the philosopher of metaphors. For him, the human being is a metaphor creating being. Knowledge comes through metaphors as through rationalizing, demonstrating, or pragmatically perceiving and analyzing the facts. The philosopher noticed at some point that even a corner stone thinker as Heidegger could be read, as lacking meaning from a positivist or neopositivist standpoint, and that generally, not much would stand up from such a perspective. Only by our inherent creativity, we can hope to leap from the “enstatic” to the “ecstatic” intellect, the one able to acquire knowledge beyond logic. Only from going beyond what Blaga names the “fanic”, or the more or less raw material of observation, within the “cryptic”, or, to make more sense in English, within the encoded, intricated core of an open mystery. Our “minus knowledge” the one that goes rather beyond than against general logic is the hope to leap into another dimension, where other people experiences to us, where we encounter other vocabularies, where the humanity of other people suffering and humiliation becomes intelligible even in different vocabularies than our own. I am as well interpreting in this paper that the exposure to different vocabularies is like an exposure to mystery. But it is never easy; to understand different vocabularies is to open yourself, oneself, to alterity and to the contextualism and historicism of somebody else. Always something remains postponed, to be understand later and always something awakens in us as we encounter through (or behind?) vocabularies the complex ethical and almost religious experience of suffering and humiliation. As Wordsworth said, in a fragment I have recently discovered reading J. Sallis’ meditation on the subject of wonder and metaphysics: “As if awakened, summoned, roused, constrained,/I looked for universal things; perused/The common countenance of earth and sky.”13 In the light of Blaga’s ideas, Rorty is, paradoxically, a particular metaphysician, because he is creating a world, a world where the ironist is not king, but some sort of model. The relativism that Blaga explains as characteristic for the human being, a tragic historical being attempting to go beyond relativism, on another plan is as well characteristic for philosophy a plurality of metaphysics as “forms of literary creation, fiction and myth”, after a formula proposed by A. Botez. Of course, Rorty may have problems with this idea. The question to pose in this comparative approach of two philosophical concepts that at the first glance have 7 LUCIAN BLAGA AND RICHARD RORTY 9 nothing in common is the following: “Is ironism an awakening from ‘the infinite sleep where our being floats’”? And the entire study struggles to sustain a positive answer to this question. Blaga’s architectural complex is a celebration of ironism avant-la-lettre. The international symposium in memoriam Blaga represented in fact as well another celebration of human becoming via mystery, as an exposure to different vocabularies, emerging outside the sleep of a comfortable universalism. For as Ortega y Gasset later on Blaga understood that no metaphysics can be perfect as to be the end of philosophy and that perfection is always postponed, belonging to the absolute. All metaphysics are under the rule of the times; hence all form a philosophical string of pearls of both wisdom and errors. Imposing even more modesty on the perspective, Rorty reminds philosophers that, bottom line, they contribute to philosophy mere vocabularies. The parallel between the historical being and the ironist has its importance in the very contemporary relevance as in the hope it brings about: life brings about the opportunity to be exposed to different vocabularies, to so interesting vocabularies (read “worlds”, “ideas”) as either Blaga’s or Rorty’s. Both their thought and lives speak volumes about ironism. Approaching the parallel between ironism and the historical being, one understands that the tragic nature of the historical being is therefore counter-balanced, in a very complex and tensioned way, by the chances to live authentically as a (liberal) ironist and as an inherently creative being. NOTES 1. For instance, at the newspaper Voinþa where his first theater play Zamolxe (Adamachi Prize for debut, granted by the Romanian Academy), was published in 1921, or, for example, he also wrote for the publications “Patria”, “Gândirea”, “Adevãrul literar ºi artistic”, “Cuvântul”. 2. At the Faculty of Letters and Philosophy, Cluj University (1946–1948). 3. At the Institute of History and Philosophy, Cluj (1949–1951). 4. Actually, he was the librarian-in-chief, at the Library of the Romanian Academy, Cluj section (1951–1954). 5. L. Blaga, Schiþa unei autoreprezentãri, Bucureºti, Cartea Româneascã, 1934. 6. L. Blaga, Schiþa unei autoreprezentãri, in: A. Botez, Dimensiunea metafizicã a operei lui Lucian Blaga, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã, 1996, p. 29. 7. As E. Cassirer said: “Man has, as it were, discovered a new method of adapting himself to his environment. Between the receptor system and the effector system, which are to be found in all animal species, we find in man a third link which we may describe as the symbolic system. This new acquisition transforms the whole of 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. human life. As compared with the other animals man lives not merely in a broader reality; he lives, so to speak, in a new dimension of reality.” (An Essay on Man, 1944) L. Blaga, Despre conºtiinþa filosoficã, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 2003, p. 207, my translation. Ibidem, p. 208, my translation. Ibidem, p. 21, my translation. Rorty, R., Private Irony and Liberal Hope, in: Walter Brogan, James Risser (eds.), American Continental Philosophy. A Reader, Bloomington and Indianapolis, Indiana University Press, 2000, p. 46. For a more detailed account of integrative concepts in Blaga’s philosophy see Botez, A., Concepte integrative în Trilogia cunoaºterii, in: “Revista de filosofie”, nr. 5–6/2001, Botez, A., Un secol de filosofie româneascã, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei Române, 2005, pp. 137–142 and Botez, A., On Complementarity and Antinomy, in: “Revue roumaine des sciences sociales”, nr. 4/1986. Apud J. Sallis, Imagination, Metaphysics, Wonder, in: Walter Brogan, James Risser (eds.), American Continental Philosophy. A Reader, Bloomington and Indianapolis, Indiana University Press, 2000, pp. 15–41. 10 HENRIETA ªERBAN 8 BIBLIOGRAPHY Aluas, I. ºi Daicoviciu, H., Criteriul sociologic în stabilirea faptului istoric, in: Al. Tãnase ºi D. Hurezeanu, Filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1969. Aristotel, Metafizica, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei, 1985. Aron, Raymond, Introducere în filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 1996. Bagdasar, N., Din problemele culturii europene, Bucureºti, Societatea Românã de Filosofie, 1931. Bagdasar, N., Bucureºti, Filosofia contemporanã a istoriei, 1930. Bagdasar, N., Lucian Blaga, in: Istoria filosofiei moderne, Omagiu profesorului Ion Petrovici, Bucureºti, Societatea Românã de Filosofie, vol. V, 1941. Balotã, N., Existenþã ºi istorie, in: “România literarã” din 20.04.1978. Bãlu, I., Viaþa lui Lucian Blaga, Bucureºti, Editura Libra, 1996. Beard, Ch., Istoria ca un act al destinului, in: “American Historical Review” (A.H.R.) nr. 2/ian. 1936. Becker, C., Fiecare este propriul sãu istoric, in: A.H.R. nr. 2/ian.1932. Bergson, H., Duratã ºi simultaneitate, in: Tudor Vianu, Henri Bergson, Istoria filosofiei moderne, Bucureºti, 1939. Blaga, L., Filosofia stilului, Bucureºti, 1924. Blaga, L., Schiþa unei autoreprezentãri, Bucureºti, Cartea Româneascã, 1934. Blaga, L., Zãri ºi etape, Bucureºti, Editura Minerva, 1968. Blaga, L., Experimentul ºi spiritul matematic, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã, 1969. Blaga, L., Fiinþa istoricã, Editura Dacia, Cluj, 1977. Blaga, L., Însemnãri filosofice, Cluj, Editura Facla, 1977. Blaga, L., Trilogia culturii, in: Opere, vol. 9, Bucureºti, Editura Minerva, 1985. Blaga, L., Trilogia valorilor, in: Opere, vol. 10, Bucureºti, Editura Minerva, 1987. Blaga, L., Aspecte antropologice, Cluj, Editura Facla, 1997. Blaga, L., Despre conºtiinþa filosoficã, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 2003. Blaikie, N., Approaches to social inquiry, Polity Press, 1993. Boboc, Al., Adevãr ºi conºtiinþã istoricã. Confruntãri între hermeneuticã ºi dialecticã în metodologia ºtiinþelor umane, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1988. Boboc, Al., Blaga, Nietzsche ºi Spengler, Demersuri moderne asupra paradigmei “stil”, in: “Revista de filosofie”, nr. 2/1995. Boboc, Al., Confruntãri de idei în filosofia contemporanã, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1983. Boboc, Al., Filosofia contemporanã, Orientãri si stiluri de gândire semnificative, Bucureºti, Editura Didacticã ºi Pedagogicã, 1995. Boboc, Al., Filosofia contemporanã, Orientãri ºi tendinþe în filosofia nemarxistã a secolului XX, Bucureºti, Editura Didacticã ºi Pedagogicã, 1980. Boboc, Al., Hermeneuticã ºi ontologie. Prolegomene la o reconstrucþie modernã în filosofia culturii, Bucureºti, E.D.P., 1999. Bollnow, I. Fr., La philosophie de la vie à l’époque moderne, in: vol. Les grands courants de la pensée mondiale contemporaine. Les tendances principales, vol. I, Paris, Fischbacher, 1961. Botez, A., Revolutions — a Fundamental Concept for the Dialectical Interpretation of Scientific Growth, in: “Revue roumaine des sciences sociales”, nr. 3–4/1978. Botez, A., The History of Science and Change of Epistemological Paradigms, in: “Revue roumaine des sciences sociales”, nr. 2/1982. Botez, A., Science and Categories, in: “Revue roumaine des sciences sociales”, nr. 1–2/1985. Botez, A., Stylistic Field and Scientific Paradigms, in: “Noesis”, nr. 3/1985. Botez, A., Concepte integrative în universul spiritual, in: “Revista de filosofie”, nr. 4/1986. Botez, A., On Complementarity and Antinomy, in: “Revue roumaine des sciences sociales”, nr. 4/1986. Botez, A. Integratory Concepts in the Universe of Culture, in: “Revue roumaine des sciences sociales”, nr. 1/1987. Botez, A., Dimensiunea metafizicã a operei lui Lucian Blaga, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã, 1996. Botez, A., Metafizica, “moarte” sau resurecþie postmodernã?, in: “Revista de filosofie”, nr. 1–2/1997. Botez, A., Concepte integrative. Antice, Moderne, Postmoderne, Bucureºti, Editura Semne, 1998. Botez, A. (coord.), Realism ºi relativism în filosofia ºtiinþei contemporane, Editura DAR, 1993. Botez, A., Concepte integrative în Trilogia cunoaºterii, in: “Revista de filosofie”, nr. 5–6/2001. Botez, A., Filosofia la începutul mileniului al III-lea, in: “Contemporanul-Ideea europeanã”, nr. 5/2004. Botez, A., Un secol de filosofie româneascã, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei Române, 2005. Botez, Angela, Dumitru Ghiºe, Lucian Blaga — cunoaºtere ºi creaþie, Bucureºti, Editura Cartea Româneascã, 1979. Botez, V., Romanian Philosophers. For Reference in the World of Philosophy (Lucian Blaga, Mircea Florian, Mircea Vulcãnescu, Nae Ionescu, D.D. Roºca, D. Stãniloae), (Antologie), Bucureºti, The Foreign Languages Press Group, 1994. 9 LUCIAN BLAGA AND RICHARD RORTY Brucar, I., Fenomenul filosofic românesc, in: “Familia”, I, nr. 5–6/1934. Cassirer, E., Eseu depre om, traducere de Constantin Comºan, Bucureºti, Humanitas, 1994. Cassirer, E., The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, part IV, The Metaphysics of Symbolic Forms. Cãlinescu, G., Istoria literaturii române de la origini pânã în prezent, Bucureºti, 1941. Cioran, E., Lucian Blaga. Eonul dogmatic, in: “Revista de filosofie”, vol. XVI, 1931. Colingwood, R.G., The Idea of History, London, University Press, 1973. Culda, L., Devenirea oamenilor în procesualitatea socialã, Editura Licorna, 1997. Culda, L., Procesualitatea socialã, Editura Licorna, 1997. Danto, A., Analitical Philosophy of History, Cambridge University Press, 1968. Dewey, I., Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, New York, 1949. Dilthey, W., Der Aufbau des gestchichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenchaften in Gesammelte Schriften, VII Band Verlag von B.G. Teubner, Lepzig und Berlin, 1927, fragment (Delimitarea ªtiintelor spiritului), in: “Revista de Teorie Socialã”, nr. 2/1998, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei Române, 1998. Dilthey, W., Die geistige Welt Einleitung in die Philosophie des lebens, in: Gesammelte Werke, V Band, Erste Häfte, 6, Aufl.hrsg. von G. Misch, Vamden Hoek & Ruprecht, Göttingen, 1974. Dilthey, W., Einleitung in die Geisteswissensschaften, fragment, trad. de Al. Boboc in: “Filosofia contemporanã în texte alese ºi adnotate”, p. II, Bucureºti, 1988. Dilthey, W., Geneza hermeneuticii, trad. de Al. Boboc, in: Filosofia contemporanã. Texte alese, traduse ºi comentate de Al. Boboc ºi I.N. Roºca, Bucureºti, Editura Garamond, 1995. Dilthey, W., Trãire ºi poezie, Bucureºti, Editura Univers, 1977. Eliade, M., Aspecte ale mitului, Bucureºti, Editura Univers, 1978. Ellul, I., Tehnological Society, New York, 1964. Façon, N., Benedetto Croce, in: Estetica..., Febvre, L., Combats pour l’histoire (Introducere), Paris, 1953. Florian, M., Introducere în filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Garamond, 1996. Florian, R., Metamorfoza culturii în secolul XX, Craiova, Editura Cartea Româneascã, 1988. Freud, S., Les Théories des sciences humaines, Paris, P.U.F., 1963. Gadamer, G-H., Wahrheit und Metode. Grunzägen einer philosophichen Hermeneutik, Tübingen, 1975 Introducere, trad. de Al. Boboc, in: Filosofia contemporanã, 1995. Gardiner, P., Theories of History, Glencoe, The Free Press, III, 1959. 11 Gogoneaþã, N., Aspecte specifice ale determinismului istoric, in: Al. Tãnase , D. Hurezeanu, Filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1969. Gulian, C., Axiologie ºi istorie în gândirea contemporanã, I, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei, 1991. Hegel, G.F.W., Prelegeri de filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei, 1968. Hegel, G.F.W., ªtiinþa logicii, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei, 1962. Hempel, C.G., The function of general laws in history, New York, 1949. Hook, S., Philosophy and History, New-York, 1963. Ianoºi, I., Dicþionarul operelor filosofice româneºti, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 1997. Iorga, N., Generalitãþi privind studiile istorice, Bucureºti, 1976. Hudiþeanu, A., Oportunitatea investigãrii ºtiinþifice a ideologiilor, in: vol. Investigarea naþiunilor. Aspecte teoretice ºi metodologice, (coord. L. Culda), Bucureºti, Editura Licorna, 1998. Hurezeanu, D., Generalul ºi individualul în istorie, in: Al. Tãnase, D. Hurezeanu, Filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1969. Jaspers, K., Texte filosofice, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1986. Kant, I., Critica raþiunii pure, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã ºi Enciclopedicã, 1972. Kuhn, Th., Structura revoluþiilor ºtiinþifice, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã ºi Enciclopedicã, 1976. Lévi-Strauss, Cl., Tropice triste, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã ºi Enciclopedicã, 1968. Marga, A., Introducere în filosofia contemporanã, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã, 1988. Marrou, H.I., De la connaissance historique, Paris, Editions du Seuil, 1959. Maxim, I., Lucian Blaga, Fiinþa istoricã, in: “Orizont”, nr. 12/ian.1978. Mises, Ludwig, von, Theory and History, New Haven, 1957. Mitrea-ªerban, H.A., Ironia privatã ºi speranþa liberalã, traducere Rorty, R., Private Irony and Liberal Hope, in Walter Brogan, James Risser (eds.), American Continental Philosophy. A Reader, Bloomington and Indianapolis, Indiana University Press, 2000, pp. 44–66, pentru “Revista de filosofie”, nr. 4/1005, sub tipar. Mitrea-ªerban, H.A. , Metaphors in politics, in: “Revue Roumaine de Philosophie”, Tome 47, Nos 1–2, 2003, pp. 163–176. (an de apariþie 2004). Montogomery, J.W., Încotro se-ndreaptã istoria?, Oradea, Editura Cartea Creºtinã, 1996. Motru, C.R., Timp ºi destin, Editura Vestala, 1996 (Ed. I. Fundaþia, 1940). Musca, V., Lucian Blaga, filosof al istoriei, in: “Orizont”, nr. 13/apr.1978. Negulescu, P.P., Destinul omenirii, vol. II, Bucureºti, Editura Cugetarea, 1944. Negulescu, P.P., Scrieri inedite, II: Destinul omenirii, vol.V, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei, 1969. 12 HENRIETA ªERBAN Nietzsche, F., Naºterea tragediei, in: De la Apollo la Faust, Bucureºti, Editura Meridiane, 1978. Nowell-Smith, P.H., Are historical events unique?, New-York, 1957. Papu, E., Benedetto Croce, in: Istoria filosofiei moderne. Omagiu Profesorului Ion Petrovici, Bucureºti, Societatea Românã de Filosofie, vol. IV, 1939. Papu, E., Existenþa romanticã, Bucureºti, Editura Minerva, 1980. Popescu, I.M., O perspectivã româneascã asupra teoriei culturii ºi valorilor. Bazele teoriei culturilor ºi valorilor în sistemul lui L. Blaga, Editura Eminescu, 1980. Popper, K., Mizeria istoricismului, Bucureºti, CEU Press, 1996. Radu, Gh., Introducere în filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Didacticã ºi Pedagogicã, 1996. Randal, J.H., jr., Nature and Historical Explanation, New-York, 1958. Ranke, L., von, Geschschite der romanichen und germanichen Völker von 1494 bis 1514, Leipzig, 1885. Read, C., The Social Responsibilities of the Historian, in: A.H.R., nr. 2/ian. 1950. Ricoeur, P., Histoire et verité, Paris, 1955. Riedel, M., Comprehensiune sau explicare?, ClujNapoca, Editura Dacia, 1989. Rorty, R., Consequences of Pragmatism, Minneapolis, 1982. Rorty, R. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1979. Rorty, R., The Linguistic Turn: Essays in Philosophical Method (1967), University of Chicago Press, 1992. Rorty, R., Contingenþã, ironie ºi solidaritate, traducere ºi note de Corina Sorana ªtefanov, studiu introductiv ºi control ºtiinþific de Mircea Flonta, în loc de postfaþã Richard Rorty despre Adevãr, Dreptate ºi “Stânga Culturalã” (discuþie cu Jõrg Lau ºi Thomas Assheuer, in: “Die Zeit”, nr. 30, 18 iulie 1997, traducere de Mircea Flonta), Bucureºti, Editura All, 1998. Rorty, R., Obiectivitate, relativism ºi adevãr. Eseuri filosofice I, traducere de Mihaela Cãbulea, studiu introductiv de Mircea Flonta, Bucureºti, Editura Univers, 2000. 10 Rorty, R., Pragmatism ºi filosofie post-nietzscheanã. Eseuri filosofice II, traducere de Mihaela Cãbulea, studiu introductiv de Mircea Flonta, Bucureºti, Editura Univers, 2000. Rorty, R., Private Irony and Liberal Hope, in: Walter Brogan, James Risser (eds.), American Continental Philosophy. A Reader, Bloomington and Indianapolis, Indiana University Press, 2000, pp. 44–66. Rowse, A.L., The Use of History, London, 1946. Schaff A., Istorie ºi adevãr, Cluj-Napoca, Editura Politicã, 1982. Spengler, O., Declinul Occidentului, Craiova, Editura Beladi, 1996 ºi Le déclin de l’Occident, Esquisse d’une morphologie de l’histoire universelle, traducere de acad. M. Tazerout, vol. I–IV. Paris, Gallimard, 1931. Stahoski, N., Despre statutul structural ºi funcþional al culturii, in: “Revista de sociologie”, nr. 5–6/1997. Tãnase, Al., Despre natura faptului istoric, in: Al. Tãnase, D. Hurezeanu, Filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1969. Tãnase, Al., Introducere în filosofia culturii, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã, 1968. Tãnase, Al., Lucian Blaga — filosoful poet, poetul filosof, Bucureºti, Cartea Româneascã, 1977. Toynbee, A., Un studiu asupra istoriei, vol. I–II, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 1997. Tudosescu, I., Lucian Blaga, Concepþia ontologicã, Bucureºti, Editura Fundaþiei “România de mâine”, 1999. Vianu, T., Filosofia stilului la Lucian Blaga in: “Gândirea”, vol. IV, nr. 3/15 nov. 1924. Vianu, T., Filosofia culturii, in: Opere, 8, Editura Minerva, 1979. Vianu, T., Raþionalism si istorism, in: Opere, 8, 1979. Vulcãnescu, M., Pentru o nouã spiritualitate filosoficã. Dimensiunea româneascã a existenþei, Bucureºti, Editura Eminescu, 1992. Walsh, W.H., Philosophy of History, Harper Torchbooks, 1960. Xenopol, A.D., Scrieri sociale ºi filosofice, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã, 1967. Zamfir, C., Filosofia istoriei, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã ºi Enciclopedicã, 1980. THE ANALYSIS OF POPPER ON MARX’S METHOD. SOME NONCONFORMIST REMARKS ANA BAZAC The paper does not discuss the psychological roots of Popper’s theory about Marx’s method. It only puts the arguments of Popper in front of some elements of Marx’s method. Just because Popper did not change his opinion about Marx’s method after his writings during World War II, these ones, expressed in his volume, The Open Society and Its Enemies, are so important for the characterisation of a special manner of social thinking. A. As we know, Popper defined himself as critical rationalist. This means “attitude of readiness to listen to critical arguments and to learn from experience”. Concerning the human behaviour, the rationalist one means to follow his/her own interests. The life/practice is what teaches us, and we can say that truth issues just from this complex feed back between our behaviour and its results. It is not here the place to discuss the conception of Popper about truth, but Popper “argues that the adoption of rationalism as an approach to life generally is something that should be advocated because it leads to a better society, but it can advocated on grounds which are not only ethical, but ultimately irrational… not only because we have no guarantee that rational methods will bring us to the truth, but also because there is something paradoxical in the very attempt to produce a reasoned defence of reason itself. So, for Popper, rationalism, however desirable it may be, is ultimately a matter of irrational faith”.1 Popper was the heir of the long tradition of western philosophy which, because of the historical conditions of the separation between the physical and spiritual labour — and, at the same time, between the command and the execution2 — developed in “the interminable succession of philosophical dualisms and dichotomies...: theory/practice; thought/being; subject/object; for-itself/in-itself; world-views/factual knowledge; immanence/transcendence; noumenal/phenomenal; essence/appearance; essence/existence; form/content; value/fact; ought/is; reason/emotion; Reason/Understanding; freedom/necessity; individual/species; private/public; political/social; state/civil society; de jure/de facto…”.3 For this reason, and even if Popper did not want to separate the functional aspects of the social system from its dynamics, he did not want to derive values from facts, to put the system under question either. Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 13–23, Bucharest, 2005. 14 ANA BAZAC 2 Rejecting the possibility of a “global alternative to the established order”4, the pattern of conceiving the system was, with Popper too, to focus on the instrumental/functional plane and, at the same time, to transfer the axiological dimension to a separate realm of values.5 But, thinking he had a support in Heisenberg’s principle of incertitude, Popper promoted ultimately a weak social theory. We could observe here the “malefic” sense of philosophy (and, concretely, of political philosophy): just because of these separations and dichotomies, it was and yet could be separated from the real processes and problems, neglecting them by covering them with a dense curtain. Popper illustrated the tension, even if he declared himself as a critical rationalist, between “the structural (or ‘synchronic’, ‘systematic’, ‘structural/functional’) and the historical (or ‘dyachronic’, ‘genetic’) aspects of theory”.6 Reducing everything to its present functionality, Popper also ignored that the above-mentioned compartmentalization — functional and axiological — is “an ideologically motivated reduction”.7 B. Demonstrating a high scientific sincerity, Popper began by underlining that a return to the pre-Marx level of social science is unconceivable, after Marx applied rationalist methods to the more pressing problems of social life. But “Hegel’s and Marx’s historicist philosophies are characteristic products of their time — a time of social change”. While Plato reacted to this situation by attempting to arrest all change”, Hegel and Marx proved a great “love of change”.8 This excessive love of change seemed to Popper ambiguous. He decomposed Marx’s theory of change and showed its antagonisms, as he understood them. But Popper did not go farther than Marx: even if he is situated at the left of neo-liberalists like Hayek9, he remained inside the common mainstream social perspective. C. Popper developed an intellectual critique of Marx’s method. And he did so neither as economist, nor as a researcher in social philosophy. His specialty was philosophy of science. He did not spend as much time as the theoretical economists to analyze the tendencies from the post-Marx economy and society. For this reason, he took over the common right-wing type clichés: 1. the theory of Marx = Marxism/vulgar Marxism10, 2. the theory of Marx involves dictatorship, so 3. the theory of Marx would have been the ground of Stalinism. These conclusions were drawn because Popper was convinced that “there is a basic unity of method between the natural and the social sciences” and “that the logic of explanation is the same in both”.11 And, for the object of the social sciences is the study of unique phenomena, whose elements are the human beings, these sciences do concentrate on “how people’s motives are partially determined by the institutions and traditions …and second on the framing laws which capture the way in which so much of what actually happens is due to the unintended consequences of the actions of individuals”.12 Finally here, because a rigorous science is based on a rigid determinism, and because society does not admit this type of determinism, Popper arrived at the conclusion that the social science studies the unintended consequences of people’s actions and, thus, this science does not imply the moment of prognosis. 3 THE ANALYSIS OF POPPER ON MARX’S METHOD 15 Popper accused Marx to be a false prophet of the course of history, who made people believe that the historical prophecy would be the scientific manner to approach the social problems. Popper accused Marx of having made predictions for the future, especially for revolutions, which did not come true, and that he did not give the theoretical ground for this future, concretely for the Russian revolution. But: 1. Marx did not make any kinds of prophecies. 2. Especially Marx warned that the transformation of capitalism would last. As far as in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts from 184413, Marx said that communism, just because it will be the logical result of the development of productive forces, and just because it will suppress the social causes of the alienation of man, a. it will be a transformation of the economicsocial system, and not only of political regimes or forms of government, so b. this transformation needs and will be only at the world scale (we do not discuss here the problem of the local origin of the transformation), and c. if some local concrete historical conditions generated a revolution — as in Russia in 1917 — this revolution would not lead to communism; on the contrary, it would lead to the crude communism, rather an attempt at communism than a phase of it, we could now say, to Stalinism.14 For this reason, even if Marx was very impressed by the French bourgeois revolution and sometimes, especially when he was young, he abandoned himself to the idea that the structural contradictions of capitalism already would have been aged, in his theoretical works never followed this supposition. On the contrary, he stressed that a system never disappears before the old one develops its contradictions to their ultimate consequences and, at the same time and through this fact, it develops, involuntarily and from its inner logic, some elements (bricks) of the new system. The logic of Marx’s theory does not allow deducing the prediction of the coming of a revolution in some years. 3. Moreover, we know, and professionals of the philosophy of science have to know, that in science the verification can occur even after hundreds of years. And we do not speak about revolutions as such, because these ones are phenomena generated by past states of things, but about all the phenomena which constitute the inherent transformation of the present system, as the past systems were transformed too. Popper admitted, with Marx, that there are sociological laws, but not the ones concerning history as such. The future is open, as Marx also thought and wrote, but Popper advanced only an abstract image of the improvements of democracy and welfare as a result of the political intelligence of the ruling elite (under the former pressures of trade-unions and with the help of the social-democrate parties which alternate in a peaceful and honourable manner). The pattern of Popper’s theory was the democracy in the developed countries. He took into consideration neither the relationships between these countries and “the rest” (there relationships being an essential condition of the level and living standard in the Centre type countries) nor the historical conditions which permitted the Western model of democracy and welfare, thus the historical character of this 16 ANA BAZAC 4 model. It is an irony that Popper, who criticised Hegel, took over the pattern of the “end of history”, the last and highest level of social development as the Western type democracy. Popper’s sociological laws happened inside this pattern. But without considering the essential social interests and positions, which move the actions and conscience of men (even if the latter are not conscious about this), and without considering the dialectics of needs and productive forces, which just configure the social interests and positions, the future is not open: it simply is immobile, the same as it ever was, in a kind of éternel retour which signifies that we can never understand history (not because it would be created and directed by God, but) because everything is new and, at the same time, the same as ever, the ceaseless running of individuals in the same manner and in an incomprehensible world. Popper suggested that Marx (this time equated with vulgar Marxists) would have overrated the importance of economic conditions “in any particular case” just because “the general importance of Marx’s economism can hardly be overrated”.15 If we are to make a difference between the theory of Marx and the vulgate, we observe that, as to the importance accorded by Marx to ideology and the analysis of false and true conscience, many analyses of particular policies, ideologies and culture show that Marx only stressed economy, which was not considered before him as an explanatory factor of social behaviours and course of history. But, as many researchers in the field of politics do, Popper accused Marx that his economism and theory about the economic structure and the juridical and political superstructures annul the autonomy of politics and its power to govern and manage things in a creative manner: “The most important consequence is that all politics, all legal and political institutions as well as all political struggles, can never be of primary importance. Politics are impotent. They can never alter decisively the economic reality.”16 Or, Marx did not depreciate politics and, as we saw, all sorts of ideology. On the contrary, he spent so much time to create the First International just because he knew and theorised that workers had to struggle for their rights, and first for political rights. But the analysis of Marx showed — and not only because in his time the political regimes were authoritarian and workers had no rights — that politics, even if it changed political regimes and leaderships, could not go farther than the economic relationships. Marx never neglected the importance of ‘formal liberty’, as Popper said Marxists do.17 Stressing the importance and superiority of capitalism — even because it gave rights to the bourgeoisie — Marx knew, through the analyses of the social and political relationships in Louis Bonaparte’s France too, that the political struggle leads to the conquest of liberties and this conquest is very dear. But there is no political liberty which could change in a fundamental manner the economic relations. The Western welfare state was an example of the high level of political and social liberties, but capitalism does not mean at all only a country, or the Western type capitalism. D. Popper’s representation about capitalism was simple: because of fascism, the democratic capitalism was the best type of social organization, in opposition 5 THE ANALYSIS OF POPPER ON MARX’S METHOD 17 to fascism=communism. He thus shared the theory which equates the socialeconomic system (for example, capitalism) and the political regime (democracy and dictatorship). But these entities are not the same. In capitalism there were both democracy and dictatorship. These political regimes were and are the result of relations of forces inside the capitalist organisation. Marx warned that if the objective conditions for communism — the high level of productive forces everywhere — did not exist, neither the social system would be communist, nor the political regime would be democratic. (It would be, as it was, Stalinism). For this reason, Stalinism was not the result of Marx’s theory (as Popper thought), but of the historical conditions of the 20th century: the specific conditions of a huge but backward country like Russia, suffering from the Centre-Periphery structural capitalist relations, and the conditions of capitalism whose development of productive forces began to surpass the capitalist frame of economic relations (the first World War being the proof). Stalinism was an attempt to change a system which could not be changed yet. There could have been an alternative to capitalism, but this alternative could be, as Marx stressed, only communism. On the other hand, fascism was just the capitalist solution to the deep contradictions between the level of productive forces, including the labour force, and the constraining frame of capitalist relations: because of the significant pressure of the labour force for social and economic rights, the maintaining of the system as such, as well as because of the need of some countries like Germany to develop more rapidly to conquer a world dominant position, a dictatorial political regime at its highest level, fascist totalitarianism, seemed indeed to show the way. Thus fascism was the means to solve the problems of capitalism, and at the ideological level it was the issue of radical/excessive capitalist theories like racism, authoritarianism, elitism, individualism and irrationalism. By the same token, even if Stalinism (as a political regime) and fascism had common features — as the theorists of totalitarianism showed — they were not equivalent: they did not derive from the same causes and had not the same aims. Moreover, the concept of Stalinism does not cover only the Stalinist political regime but also the Stalinist economic system: an isotope of capitalism, and not at all socialism or communism. E. Letting alone this aspect, Popper’s representation followed the common theory of “capitalism in a single country” — if we can paraphrase the expression of Trotsky about Stalinism as “socialism in a country” — i.e., the “model” of capitalism was, obviously, the developed Western countries, by ignoring the fact that capitalism was and is a world system which developed through the CentrePeriphery relationships in their whole complexity. But not only did Popper make this type of design about society. The time he wrote The Open Society… yet was the time of national capital: the time of national relationships between capital and the labour force. From this type of relationships derived all the other relations and institutions. Ultimately, the level of productive forces — we must not forget that it was the time of the first industrial revolution, even if in America the level of this revolution was already 18 ANA BAZAC 6 the one of Fordism — was the important cause which determined the need to keep the compulsion of labour force and, from this need, the mystifying ideologies, contradictory institutions and savage wars. The image of Stalinists about society was just one of “capitalism in a single country” type. The best ideologists of the left — excepting Trotsky — even if highly preoccupied about the destiny of the workers, the poor and the social problems, knew that all these could be approached only inside the homo homini lupus relationships between countries.18 This deep contradiction between the organisation of social relationships inside a country and, on the other hand, the organisation of international relationships was the sign of the not yet “aged” time for communism. In that time, the efficient left was the one which fought for the welfare for its own working class inside the nation-state. As we know, this tactics was victorious in the western developed countries. But just for this type of victory, socialdemocracy had to support the general right-wing policies: the social-democrat behaviour before World War I is significant. Thus, from a theoretical standpoint, social-democracy was contradictory: on the one hand, it waved slogans about the substitution of capitalism with a more egalitarian and democratic system; on the other hand, it was “yellow”, interested only about the level of living of those who voted it: the industrial workers of the developed countries. Neither the famous internationalist slogan from the Communist Manifesto: Proletarians from all the countries, unite! nor the dismantling of capitalism — and this is possible, according to Marx, only at the world scale — were yet of the day and, obviously, the goals of the efficient left. Consequently, almost every one who thought of the social problems in a realistic manner forgot (for the objective conditions pushed him/her to forget) a. the systemic conception of Marx about society (and capitalism, of course), b. the interdependences of Centre and Periphery (to use an easy but later expression), c. the inner world logic of capital and d. the fact that any national working class could not liberate itself without contributing to the liberation of the other national working classes. So, if someone fought capitalism he/she fought capitalism “in a country”, if someone defended capitalism he/she defended it “in a country”. And, as we know, “capitalism” meant the advanced capitalism, the smiling face of Janus, the beautiful shop-window of this system, which covered the dark one. (But Marx himself paid attention mostly to the advanced countries: England and America were his models, and not Eastern Europe, Russia, Latin America or India, could someone say. Of course, we respond, but this happened not in order to neglect the colonies and the lagging-behind countries — as did and do so many “realist” theorists — nor to sing the model of “socialism in a single country”, but to demonstrate 1. that the logic of capital and the logic of the development of productive forces are the most visible in the advanced countries — which serve as a theoretical model — because here the contradictions of capitalism are deeper and liberated of any outmoded ballast (and also because in these countries the illusions existed that the economic development would bring welfare for all) and 2. that the logic of capital and the logic of the development 7 THE ANALYSIS OF POPPER ON MARX’S METHOD 19 of productive forces integrates the entire world, the colonies and lagging-behind countries also, in a world, interconnected capitalism, from the viewpoint of productive forces (of civilisation, even if yet at different levels) and from the viewpoint of intertwined capitalist interests and relations. So, Marx never considered capitalism “in a country”.) It was, obviously, a concrete conditioning of the general conception about “capitalism in a single country”, and rather in a western country. Popper and the other thinkers grew up and lived in these countries when rulers transferred a part of their benefices from the world economic relations, where they dominated, to the ruled of these blessed advanced countries. Popper could not be an exception to this entire post-Marx period. Only very few thinkers — and between them the nomina odiosa Lenin and Trotsky19 — conceived that, a. as Marx said, only when the past system have developed all the conditions it could inside its structural relations a new system can rise (and in the first moments, inside the old one), and that, b. people who are concerned with the life of “the losers” have to be the most consistent they can: they have not only to not support the inter-capitalist wars, to always emphasize the interconnection between capitals but, on the other hand, between different national working people, to always struggle for the human rights everywhere, and not only at home. In the theory of these thinkers, the falling of Stalinism — determined by the consensus of the Stalinist political bureaucracy and the level of world capital — was a necessary fact (even if painful for many people), just because without its enemy, the world capitalism could emphasize its inner contradictions in an unveiled manner. F. “Popper’s social science is an attempt to avoid various extremes. It is individualistic without being psychologistic. It admits the autonomy of sociology, in saying that men are formed by traditions and institutions, but attempts to avoid holism by explaining events as the consequences of individual actions. It attempts to unify the methods of natural science and social science, and so to avoid the incursion of the mystical into social science, but admits the agent’s perception of his situation as an essential part of any explanation.”20 Thus Popper did not pay attention to the interests which are, of course, not only individual. The interests of every human being are very different rather from the super-position of different kinds of interests at the same time: to have an interesting and creative activity, to have a job, to have a family, children, money to nurse them, to travel, to pay the housing, to be happy, to be healthy, to be saved from catastrophes, and so on. Every interest enters into contact and clashes with the interests of other people (and, naturally, even with other type of interests of the same person).21 From these connections and clashes issue the unintended consequences, which were studied, as Popper underlined, by Marx as one of the first forerunners. But, at the same time, people have the same position facing many criteria: many are wage earners and not employers, or live in an advanced country or in a backward one, or live in a time when, to make war, people are educated in the hate of foreigners, and so on. Thus, the general, i.e., different social groups/classes, interests are not “superhuman factors” from 20 ANA BAZAC 8 which one could deduce that history would be determined in an automatic inherent manner. Every human being conducts him or, herself, in a rational manner, i.e., following his or her interests in particular conditions and under the influence of particular situations and institutions. But society is not a clash of atoms in a Brownian movement, certainly not “individual + individual + individual”. It is the connection between groups, each formed by unique and non-repeatable human beings, but which have also common interests, plans and dreams. By denying that collectives (states, nations, classes, etc.) do anything, Popper contradicted his conception about the autonomy of sociology and the rejection of psychologism. Discussing about institutions and traditions, do these ones not influence social groups, even if it is possible that every man could perceive this influence in another way because he is influenced also by other situations? For this reason, and not being an economist nor a sociologist, Popper was not interested in the social reproduction of these institutions, traditions and interests, and nor in the inner contradictions of this complex process. Even if his main objective was not the analysis of society, but of scientific knowledge, his model of society was a puzzle of unintended consequences of clashes and co-existence of human beings and the explanation of society was the reduction of the social complexity to a puzzle of unintended consequences. Paradoxically, even if Popper hardly criticised Heidegger, his philosophy of nothingness, anguish and fear of death, the image of society in Heidegger philosophy and in Popper is similar enough: many human beings, conscientious or not, even if rational, live, run, suffer, die in the human anthill. Every one for his own reasons, for his own survival — this is the only rule. It’s not too much: humans are reduced to matter, to dust, to nothing; neither their conscience nor creations can change this senseless existence. G. Popper was, however, contradictory: on the one hand, he said we cannot deduce the future from the past — i.e., from the above-mentioned separations and dichotomies —, even if, as Marx noted explicitly, society has no laws as in nature but only tendencies, resulted just from the clashes of different social groups.22 And Popper agreed with the tendencies. But, for him, the future is not only open — we have to underline that, just because of the tendencies, and not natural/mechanical laws, and because of the unexpected consequences23, the future is also open for Marx: communism is not an ideal and “the end of history”, but only “a real movement which suppresses the present status” — it is absolutely accidental.24 On the other hand, the future is the result of a step by step social engineering. And, from this one, communism could be possible25, but what is important to Popper is rather to show the “historicism” of Marx. History has no sense, “has no meaning”26, said Popper. There is “only an indefinite number of histories of all kinds of aspects of human life”.27 It is true28, and Marx did not say a different thing, neither from the standpoint of the knowledge of society (and the above-mentioned opinion just about this knowledge was) nor from the one of the objective social processes. Popper’s critique on historicism — the manner of predicting future from the past, on the basis of laws — was and can be seen from two standpoints: the one 9 THE ANALYSIS OF POPPER ON MARX’S METHOD 21 is the scientific will to do away with the dogmatic and mechanic manner of thinking society, professed either by vulgar Marxist sociologists or by religion29 or even by liberalism, which repeats the pattern of Hegel’s thinking about “the end of history” in the best of all possible worlds; this standpoint is very precious for all of us, for Popper’s stressing on the responsibility of mankind, decisionmakers and social scientists; the other is the ideological position of both liberalism and conservatism in front of the challenge of alternatives to the capitalist system. As I showed, a critical rationalism — as was the one of Marx — put under question the alternatives themselves, and not only the given system. But if we start from the premise that there are no alternatives, and that we can only deduce and produce better functioning hoping that this one will annul the contradictions and consequences of the structural relationships of the system and will improve it, our theory is not satisfactory. H. The critique we made on Popper’s conception about Marx’s method cannot, however, exclude his excellent observations about the fact that “class struggle as such does not always produce lasting solidarity among the oppressed”30 or that the coming of “the new ruling class of the new society”31, or “that a whole host of possible historical developments may follow upon a victorious proletarian revolution”, or that “we should also recognise that the allegedly scientific prophecy provides, for a great number of people, a form of escaping from our responsibilities”32, observations which left type politicians, from the East European countries especially, would have taken into account. I mentioned above that this new ruling class existed in Stalinism just because Stalinism was not, and could not be, communism/socialism. But even a rightwing type critique should have been taken into account. From a strict theoretical standpoint, nothing forbids in and with Marx’s method to surpass it, to go farther. The fact that this did not happen was determined by the historical conditions, and not by Marx’s method. Only after a more or less long period, when many problems agglomerated and the contradictions of the “normal functioning” were revealed, people and thinkers can analyse society from a “radical” critical standpoint. But the taking over of the right-wing type clichés from the most part of social theorists is a proof of weakness: if these clichés seemed, at the time when Popper wrote The Open Society…, to be not too harmful, even if at that time Popper defended the system which did not yet offer welfare state, but only political democracy, nowadays, with all the acquisitions in management, these clichés are the sign of crisis in social theory, and also in society. But this aspect is no more the goal of this paper. NOTES 1. Anthony O’Hear, Karl Popper, London, Boston and Henley, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980, p. 147. 2. See Aristotle and the labour force. Aristotle’s tradition in the present-day industrial revolution ideology, in: “Revue roumaine de philosophie”, 1–2, 2004, pp. 87–106. 3. István Mészáros, A key problem of method: dualism and dichotomies in philosophy and social theory in capital’s epoch, in: “Critique”, 22 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. ANA BAZAC (Great Britain) no. 34, 2004, p. 73. These dichotomies remain “unintelligible without the manifold practical dualisms and antinomies of the socio-economic order”, ibidem. Ibidem, p. 33. Ibidem, p. 31: “where their confrontation cannot endanger the practical functioning of the… structure”. Ibidem, p. 29. Ibidem, p. 46. Karl R. Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945), volume II, The High Tide of Prophecy: Hegel, Marx and the Aftermath, Princeton, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1971, p. 212. It is not unsignificant that The Open Society …is dedicated to Hayek. Even if he saw the difference between Marx and the vulgar Marxism and criticised this one. Anthony O’Hear, Karl Popper, London, Boston and Henley, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980, p. 161. Ibidem, p. 162. Unfinished, written by Marx in April-August 1844, the Economic-Philosophical Manuscripts from 1844 were published for first time in 1927, and after in 1932, in German, in Moscow. „As such it appears in a two-fold form: on the one hand, the dominion of material property bulks so large that it wants to destroy everything which is not capable of being possessed by all as private property. It wants to disregard talent, etc., in an arbitrary manner. For it the sole purpose of life and existence is direct, physical possession. The category of the worker is not done away with, but extended to all men. The relationship of private property persists as the relationship of the community to the world of things… The community is only a community of labour, and equality of wages paid out by communal capital — by the community as the universal capitalist. Both sides of the relationship are raised to an imagined universality — labour as the category in which every person is placed, and capital as the acknowledged universality and power of the community… The first positive annulment of private property — crude communism — is thus merely a manifestation of the vileness of private property, which wants to set itself up as the positive community system.”, Marx, cited work, http://www.marxists.org/glossary/frame.htm Popper, op. cit., p. 107. Ibidem, p. 119. Ibidem, p. 127. This image was prefigured by More in his Utopia (1516). As we remember, even if the private property was seen as the main cause of evils and was suppressed in that blessed special island, the interest of utopians was to save their status quo, even through perverse diplomacy and 10 wars, and not at all to develop it by “exporting” utopia. See Thomas Morus, L’Utopie, Paris, Lumen Animi, 1935. 19. Lenin wrote a lot and explicitly about the state capitalism which had to be constructed in the backward Russia, after October 1917: even if the slogans and values were socialist — egalitarian — the real productive relationships could be only capitalist type; the compulsion of the labour force, just for faster develop the country and improve the living conditions (especially the cultural ones), had to be hard, and only the destruction of privileges of the political — state and party — bureaucracy could have soothed this compulsion. Why state capitalism and not state socialism, as later Trotsky considered USSR — as a degenerated worker state — ? Just because: 1. Russia, being a so backward country, could not transform at once into a socialist country, only in the most advanced at that time form of capitalism, the state capitalism, which did begin first in the Soviet Russia, after in Sweden (where the social-democrats gained the power in 1932 with the programme Gunar Myrdal did), then in the Nazi Germany and later in Great Britain (of Keynes) and in the United States of Roosevelt’s New Deal. 2. Russia — but any other country — could not construct socialism in a country without, if not the world, at least the European milieu being socialist. Just after it was clear that the revolution in Germany revolution failed, Lenin was more convinced that the only fate of the Soviet Russia is to become a model of rapid but at the same time democratic development of a welfare state. As we yet know, that could not take place: Stalin developed Russia with the help of political bureaucracy and in a totalitarian manner. And the “communist” Russia broke down not only because of the non-democratic and bureaucratic political regime which was no more tolerated by people, and not only because of the political, economical and ideological pressures from the West, but because of the coincidence of the interests of the world capital and, on the other hand, the ones of the bureaucracy which desired remain a dominant class and this could no more be without the help of the western, world capitalism. Concerning Trotsky, he did not see that Stalin — as the representative of the political centre (of the bureaucracy which wanted practical socialism but Trotsky knew that the only fate of the practical socialism is the new internationalism. If the critique of Stalinism was not quite adequate, the initiative of a fourth International, the permanent underlining of the absolute need of internationalism as the way to fight world capitalism, made Trotsky the more important descendant of Marx, nearby Lenin. 11 THE ANALYSIS OF POPPER ON MARX’S METHOD 20. Ibidem. 21. See, for example the often met motive, from the old classical literature to the present movies, of the clash between passion and reason. 22. Because, as Marx said, people make their own history but only inside the conditions they live, so under the influences of institutions and traditions and through driving at theirs own goals, but all these individual aims cannot unweave their common specific goals, as different kinds of groups. For Marx and for the logic of the historical societies where were and are social hierarchy, the most important division in groups (classes) is the one of the position towards the ownership of means of production. But this division is not the single and, more, it manifests also through other division — as gender, race, nations, countries, different professional groups — in different covered or explicit manners. 23. Just as the present theories of chaos, complexity and bifurcation demonstrated with their mathematical apparatus. 24. As we see, the present social organisation can lead to the destruction of society and nature. But there are also tendencies which oppose this. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 23 These tendencies are internal to the logic of survival of the ruling classes, but also internal to the entire humankind. The first tendency is also internal to the logic of capital. Karl Popper, op. cit., p. 139. Ibidem, p. 269. Ibidem, p. 270. From the standpoint of the physics of universe, Roger Penrose and Stephen Hawking demonstrated the same thing: that there is an infinite number of histories of universe, and only this representation could explain, in a unitary manner the space, the time and the matter. The serious and determinate critique on the religious historicism made from Popper an ally of non-conformist thinkers. For this reason, the mainstream political theory does not stop on and neglect the uncomfortable alliance of Popper with the heretical social theory. In fact, nor the critical rationalism, assumed by Popper, is more pleasant to the radical conservative theory. Karl Popper, op. cit., p. 139. Ibidem, p. 138. Ibidem. RAWLS, NOZICK Y PETTIT. UNA VISIÓN COMPARATIVA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA JUSTICIA RÃZVAN PANTELIMON Voy a comenzar mi análisis con el libro de John Rawls, Una teoría de la Justicia, uno de los más importantes libros de la teoría política del siglo XX. Después voy a presentar la visión de Nozick, que es una crítica a la propuesta de Rawls, pero en el mismo tiempo un intento de construir una nueva teoría de una justicia retributiva. Al final voy a hablar sobre el libro de Phillipe Pettit, Republicanismo, subtitulado Una teoría sobre la libertad y el gobierno. A través de su libro A Theory of Justice, John Rawls enfoca la discusión sobre la libertad en la zona de lo político: la justicia no es considerada una virtud de los caracteres humanos o una calidad de las acciones individuales, sino es vista como una calidad de una sociedad. Rawls no pone el problema si una persona, una acción o el resultado de una acción son justos o injustos, sino una sociedad es o no justa. El libro de Rawls argumenta a favor de una teoría de la justicia, una teoría que debe explicar que denominamos una sociedad justa. La primera parte del trabajo — Teoría — muestra brevemente el marco teórico y después desarrolla los principales argumentos a favor de esto. La segunda — Instituciones — demuestra como se puede aplicar la teoría a los casos particulares, como la idea de tolerancia, la idea de merito moral o la idea de desobediencia civil. La parte final — Fines — habla de la concepción de bien del individuo y el papel de esta concepción en la justificación de la teoría de la justicia propuesta en el comienzo. La concepción sobre la libertad desarrollada por Rawls en Una teoría de la Justicia debe ser el basamento de una sociedad bienordenada. Entonces Rawls busca a encontrar los principios de la justicia social, es decir los principios que son criterios de evaluación de la justicia de una sociedad, y no de la justicia de los actos particulares de unos individuos particulares. Eso significa que el objeto de los principios de la justicia es la estructura primaria de una sociedad, es decir la manera de que se integran los principales instituciones sociales en una esquema de cooperación. Esta concepción sobre la justicia se basa en la visión de la sociedad como una asociación de personas que cooperan para el bien mutuo. Resulta que es caracterizada por el conflicto y en el mismo tiempo por una identidad de intereses. Es una identidad de intereses porque la cooperación social hace que cada miembro de la sociedad tenga una vida mejor Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 24–34, Bucharest, 2005. 2 UNA VISIÓN COMPARATIVA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA JUSTICIA 25 que la podría tener si vivía sólo. El conflicto de intereses aparece sobre la distribución de los recursos obtenidos como resultado de la cooperación. Los principios de la justicia son necesarios para determinar como se van distribuir esos recursos. La concepción general de Rawls sobre la justicia es: “Todos los valores sociales — libertad y oportunidad, ingreso y riqueza, así como las bases sociales y el respeto a sí mismo — habrán de ser distribuidos igualitariamente a menos que una distribución desigual de alguno o de todos estos valores redunde en una ventaja para todos. La injusticia consistirá entonces, simplemente, en las desigualdades que no benefician a todos.”1 Pero esa concepción es mejor conocida como los dos principios de la libertad de Rawls. El primer principio consiste en: “Cada persona ha de tener un derecho igual al esquema más extenso de libertades básicas iguales que sea compatible con una esquema semejante de libertades para los demás.” El segundo tiene dos partes: “Las desigualdades sociales y económicas habrán de ser conformadas de modo tal que a la vez que: a) se espere razonablemente que sean ventajosas para todos, b) se vinculen a empleos y cargos asequibles para todos.”2 Los principios de Rawls parten de la suposición de que todos los miembros de la sociedad, sin tener en cuenta sus herencias naturales o la posición social, tienen el mismo derecho de gozar de los beneficios que resultan de la cooperación social, porque en la definición de la sociedad todos son tratados como personas libres y iguales. La conclusión que debemos extraer de aquí no es que una distribución justa de los bienes primarios es una igual, sino que la distribución igual de los bienes primarios no debe ser justificada. Debemos justificar una distribución inegal, si aceptamos las desigualdades, esas deben ser justificadas, debemos mostrar que son justas. Es lo que hacen los dos principios: el primero se refiera a la distribución de la libertad, mientras que el segundo se refiere a la distribución a) del ingreso y b) de los chances de ocupar una posición en una institución. Esta argumentación tiene un problema importante: ¿Qué se pasa en los casos cuando la misma medida respecta un principio pero infringe al otro? Para resolver ese problema necesitamos una regla de orden entre los principios que pueda indicar que principio debemos respectar el primero. Para Rawls la prioridad la tiene la libertad: debemos respectar en primer lugar el primer principio. La libertad no puede ser restringida con la justificación del aumento de las ventajas económicas o sociales. La restricción de una libertad puede ser justificada sólo si eso fortalece todo el sistema de libertades. Una segunda regla de prioridad indica que: a) la prioridad de la justicia sobre la eficiencia y el bienestar y b) la prioridad de la igualdad de chances sobre el principio de la diferencia: una desigualdad de chances es justificada sólo si tiene como efecto el aumento de los chances de los mas desventajados. Rawls imagina un procedimiento de justificación de esos dos principios, procedimiento que hace que la teoría de Rawls pueda ser vista como una forma del contractualismo, donde la idea básica es que los principios de la justicia son objeto de un acuerdo original. Los principios que van a gobernar la estructura 3 RÃZVAN PANTELIMON 26 básica de la sociedad, deben ser elegidos en el correspondiente rawlsian del estado natural y sólo en ese caso pueden ser justificados. En la visión de John Gray, “El enfoque contractualista, que se encuentra en su forma más plausible y sólida en el trabajo de John Rawls, aparta el rudimentario colectivismo moral de Mill, y abandona la preocupación por el fomento del bienestar general. El enfoque contractualista de Rawls es auténticamente individualista, ya que confiere al individuo en la posición original un veto en contra de las políticas que maximizarían el bienestar general a costa de limitar la libertad y dañar los intereses de algunos.”3 Este estado natural en la teoría de Rawls es la posición original, la interpretación filosófica privilegiada de la situación inicial. El argumento lógico de Rawls a favor de sus dos principios es: a) como la posición original tiene algunos aspectos que son razonables para aceptarlos y b) los principios elegidos en esta situación original son los dos principios de la justicia, entonces c) los dos principios de la justicia son justificados, siendo de verdad los principios de la justicia. Las características de la posición original son: las circunstancias de la justicia, las restricciones formales del concepto de lo justo, el velo de la ignorancia, la racionalidad de los partes. Las partes en la situación original deben elegir, de una lista cerrada de principios, a aquellos que les parecen los mejores. Las circunstancias de la justicia se refieren a las condiciones normales en las cuales la cooperación humana no es sólo posible, sino necesaria. Son circunstancias objetivas (el hecho de que en el mismo territorio viven al mismo tiempo más individuos con características físicas y mentales aproximadamente iguales en condiciones de limitación de recursos) y circunstancias subjetivas (el hecho de que las partes tienen intereses y necesidades similares o complementarias, así que es posible la cooperación mutualmente ventajosa en y el hecho de que cada individuo tiene su propio proyecto de vida y metas diferentes, que tienen como resultado las demandas conflictivas sobre los recursos). Las restricciones formales del concepto de lo justo se refieren a las condiciones que deben cumplir los principios de la situación original. Esos son: 1) la condición de la generalidad (los principios deben ser formulados en términos generales, no deben ser usados nombres propios y los predicados deben expresar propiedades y relaciones generales); 2) la condición de la universalidad (los principios deben ser aplicados universalmente, eso significa que deben ser aplicables a cualquier persona); 3) la condición de la publicidad (los principios elegidos van a servir como una concepción publica de la justicia, y todos van a conocer cuales son esos); 4) la condición de la ordenación (los principios deben ofrecer un ordenamiento de las pretensiones en conflitó); 5) la condición de la definitividad (los principios deben servir como un tribunal supremo de apelación). Sólo los principios que respectan estas condiciones pueden aparecer en la lista de principios entre que deben elegir las partes en la situación original. Uno de los rasgos esenciales de esta situación de elección es el velo de la ignorancia. El tiene en cuenta el hecho de que las partes en la posición original 4 UNA VISIÓN COMPARATIVA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA JUSTICIA 27 no conocen su papel en la sociedad, los dones naturales (inteligencia, fuerza física etc.), la concepción sobre el bien, los rasgos psicológicos particulares o los rasgos de su sociedad (la situación económica y política, el nivel de civilización y de cultura). De esta manera, el velo de la ignorancia asegura que las partes esten situadas similarmente y que los principios de la justicia sean el resultado de un acuerdo correcto, un acuerdo formulado en una situación equitativa entre los individuos como personas iguales desde el punto de vista moral. Esto es lo que tiene en mente Rawls cuando denomina su teoría justicia como equidad. Las partes tienen, sin embargo, unos conocimientos generales: ellas saben que la sociedad es caracterizada por las circunstancias de la justicia y también conocen los datos generales sobre la sociedad humana (sobre política, psicología humana etc.). Las partes son caracterizadas por el tipo de racionalidad que usan para elegir; una persona racional es aquella que ordena coherente sus opciones en función de sus preferencias. Por eso es justificada la elección de bienes primarios en la situación original, porque las partes son racionales y entonces en la elección de principios buscan a mejorar sus propios intereses, pero no conocen sus propios intereses, entonces prefieren más bienes primarios porque esos son las medidas para alcanzar cualquier meta. Una característica de la racionalidad de las partes es la presunción motivacional: un individuo racional no va sufrir de envidia, las partes son mutuamente desinteresadas4, ellas no son interesadas de los intereses de los otros y no buscan tener más que otros, sino realizar mejor su propia concepción sobre el bien; entonces las partes van a buscar tener la mayor cantidad de bienes sociales, no tener más bienes que otros. Los dos principios parten de la idea de que si la situación de elección es caracterizada por algunos rasgos, entonces la elección se hace según la regla maximin, o maximum minimorum. Conforme a esta regla la elección entre dos variantes posibles se hace en función de los peores resultados que pueden tener las variantes y vamos a elegir la opción que tiene el mejor resultado negativo. En otras palabras el que raciona según esta regla prefiere evitar la peor posibilidad, que buscar a obtener la mejor. Si seguimos la regla maximin en la situación original entonces vamos a elegir los dos principios de la justicia, y para probar eso es suficiente mostrar que la situación original es caracterizada por esas características. Rawls explica que las partes en la situación original: 1) no pueden calcular las posibilidades de llegar a una posición social u otra (como resultado del velo de ignorancia), 2) las partes prefieren tener un mínimo satisfactorio más que perder el derecho igual a las libertades y 3) piensan que los otros principios tienen consecuencias intolerables. La Teoría de la justicia de Rawls es considerada el más influyente libro de filosofía política del siglo XX. No sólo fue la reformulación del principio liberal, pero en el mismo tiempo fue responsable de la revigoración de las discusiones normativas en la filosofía política en los años ’70. En el mismo tiempo el libro fue el blanco de muchas críticas. Unas de ellas han venido de las comunitaristas que piensan que esta teoría sufre de todas las 5 RÃZVAN PANTELIMON 28 faltas de las teorías liberales: no tiene en cuenta el hecho de que la sociedad es una comunidad, que los miembros de la sociedad no pueden ser vistos sólo como individuos aislados, con metas que son seguidas individualmente, sino que las metas y los intereses de los individuos son influidos por la sociedad. Otro tipo de criticas ha surgido de la parte de los liberales (aquí podemos incluir como representativo el trabajo de Robert Nozick: Anarquía, Estado y utopía) que piensan que la concepción de Rawls es un tipo de justicia redistributiva y entonces sufre de todos las faltas de esta. Esos libertarios proponen un Estado minimal, con la única meta de proteger a sus ciudadanos. Pero podemos concluir en los términos de John Gray: “Ninguna de estas dificultades compromete los logros de la teoría de Rawls en el desarrollo de una defensa individualista del orden liberal en términos contractualistas.”5 Como he dicho antes, una de las más importantes críticas de las teorías de Rawls son las de Robert Nozick en su libro Anarquía, Estado y utopía, que es considerado una de las más originales y bien sostenidas argumentaciónes productas en los últimos años en la filosofía política de orientación analítica. De un principal interés goza especialmente la concepción original de Nozick sobre la justicia distributiva como derecho (entitlement theory of justice) cuyo cuadro general y elementos principales son desarrollados en el Capitulo 7, donde hace una critica de la teoría de Rawls y sobre la cual me voy a concentrar en continuación. Anarquía, Estado y utopía contiene tres partes. En la primera Nozick demuestra que el Estado de la teoría liberal clásica, “como Estado minimal, limitado a las funciones de protección de todos sus ciudadanos contra la violencia, el robo y el fraude y la de hacer cumplir los contratos, parece ser justificado”.6 En la segunda parte Nozick afirma que todos los argumentos que tienen como meta justificar un Estado más extenso del Estado minimal son falsos, porque cualquier Estado, con atribuciones más grandes que las legítimas que el Estado minimal, viola los derechos de los individuos. La conclusión de esta parte es que el Estado minimal es el Estado con las más grandes atribuciones que pueden ser justificadas. El libro se acaba con una tercera parte donde Nozick quiere convencernos que el Estado minimal es, contrariamente a las apariencias de austeridad y extrema pobreza, un ideal por el cual vale la pena luchar. Por eso Nozick habla de un tema celebre en la filosofía política — la teoría de la utopía —, donde la parte viable de esta, que puede ser guardada y desarrollada, se refiere a la estructura del Estado minimal. El punto de partida de Nozick es una clara afirmación de los derechos de los individuos: “Los individuos tienen derechos, y hay cosas que ninguna persona o grupo puede hacerles sin violar los derechos.”7 Esta clara afirmación de los derechos de los individuos impone una reexaminación de cualquiera posibilidad de toque de sus fuerza o legitimidad; entonces la provocación del anarquista (que sostiene que el Estado, por el mantenimiento del monopolio sobre el uso de la fuerza para la protección de los ciudadanos dentro de un territorio, acaba con la violación de los derechos de los individuos, deviniendo por consiguiente inmoral) debe ser analizada atentamente. 6 UNA VISIÓN COMPARATIVA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA JUSTICIA 29 Los argumentos de la primera parte son pues orientados contra los anarquistas que se oponen a cualquier tipo de Estado. Para que la argumentación en contra de los anarquistas pueda ser convincente, el anarquista debe mostrar que: 1) el Estado puede aparecer desde el estadio de anarquía mediante un proceso que no tiene alguna etapa inmoral; 2) la producción del Estado no es el resultado de la intención de una persona; 3) la gente en una situación social definida de la existencia del Estado es en una situación mejor que la mejor situación donde pueda llegar en una sociedad sin Estado. Para demostrar eso, Nozick usa la teoría de las asociaciones de protección y de la mano invisible, que voy a analisar. Después de esta justificación del Estado minimal frente a los anarquistas, Nozick construye una teoría sobre la justicia distributiva — la justicia retributiva. Una característica del argumento de Nozick es que toda la demostración tiene un rasgo muy intenso: el acento sobre los procesos, y no sobre estructuras o metas. Su teoría del Estado puede ser caracterizada brevemente como un intento de ordenar las diversas componentes de un proceso que puede dar lugar al nacimiento de un Estado justificabil moralmente. También su teoría de la justicia retributiva tiene la misma visión general procesualista. La teoría de la justicia de Nozick introduce en la filosofía moral y en las ciencias jurídicas un nuevo paradigma definido por un proceso de un profundo carácter histórico y anti-estructural. La idea de Nozick es que “una distribución es justa si surge de otra distribución justa a través de medios legítimos”.8 Para reparar las violaciones de ese principio, Nozick se sirve de un principio de la rectificación. Este principio de la rectificación usa las informaciones históricas sobre las situaciones pasadas y las injusticias que han pasado en estas situaciones, y las informaciones sobre el Estado actual que es el resultado de estas injusticias. La rectificación de las injusticias debe tener en cuenta la estimación de la situación de hecho más probable, que es accesible desde el estadio actual y que era muy probable haberse realizado ella misma, si en el pasado no se hubiera producido la dicha injusticia. Fuertemente opuestos a los principios del resultado final o de cualquier otro Estado final “los principios históricos de justicia [retributiva] sostienen que las circunstancias o acciones pasadas de las personas pueden producir derechos diferentes o merecimientos diferentes sobre las cosas”.9 Así, guardando un crítico pero estrecho vinculo con la teoría de Locke sobre la instalación de los derechos de propiedad, la teoría de Nozick afirma que el origen de cualquier pretensión legitima sobre la propiedad de una persona sobre un objeto que no pertenece a nadie tiene su punto de partida en la combinación del trabajo de aquella persona con aquel objeto; y en la satisfacción de la condición de Locke que, después de la apropiación de aquel objeto y como consecuencia de dicha apropiación, los que no tienen más la libertad de usar de aquel objeto, no se encuentran, como resultado de esta circunstancia, en una situación peor que antes de la apropiación del objeto. También los principios de la justicia retributiva no son estructurados, lo que significa que: “la distribución debe variar de conformidad con alguna dimensión 7 RÃZVAN PANTELIMON 30 natural, con la suma de pesos de las dimensiones naturales de conformidad con un orden lexicográfico de dimensiones naturales”.10 Es muy importante destacar que aun la teoría de Nozick guarda la nota distintiva de Locke y hace del trabajo un factor importante, él no habla de la cantidad-trabajo como se pasa en la teoría marxista del valor-trabajo, porque este tipo de visión va a un principio histórico estructurado de la justicia distributiva, principio que Nozick no acepta y quiere eliminar. “Nozick puso de manifiesto agudamente las dificultades que afronta la teoría lockeana sobre la adquisición original de los derechos de propiedad, cuando en ellos se incluye el trabajo personal.”11 Si miramos las cosas más generalmente, casi cada principio de la justicia distributiva que ha propuesto es un principio estructurado. O el blanco predilecto de los ataques de Nozick es constituido por las teorías del Estado final o las teorías estructuradas de la justicia distributiva, que incluyen las teorías marxistas pero también la teoría de Rawls. Estas teorías son incompatibles con su propia teoría retributiva, porque “los principios pautados de justicia distributiva necesitan actividades redistributivas” mientras que “desde el punto de vista de una teoría retributiva la redistribución es una cuestión verdaderamente seria, que comprende, como es el caso, la violación de los derechos de las personas”.12 Si miramos desde ese punto de vista, todos los argumentos del Capitulo 7 son contra la redistribución. Un problema de las teorías de Nozick es: ¿en que medida la justificación moral del Estado minimal, por su derivación de la situación natural, como resultado de un proceso neintencionado y que no viola los derechos de los individuos, puede ofrecer bastante argumentos para la justificación de los Estados reales? Porque es poco claro por qué y especialmente como puede ser legitimado un Estado existente, aunque minimal, por el intermedio de una explicación que demuestra que un Estado minimal puede aparecer legítimamente como resultado de un proceso de tipo de “mano invisible”. Mi respuesta a esa pregunta es que la teoría de la justicia retributiva establece un estándar de la justificación moral, que es muy alto para que los Estados reales lo puedan cumplir. Así podemos ver mejor los problemas que analiza Nozick en su libro. Anarquía, Estado y utopía es un libro con un profundo carácter teórico. El autor desarrolla teorías y construye argumentos y contraargumentos muy abstractos, que demuestran que Nozick se interesa a las virtudes formales de su teoría y la posibilidad de imaginar situaciones posibles que pueden infirmar las teorías de sus oponentes y confirmar sus propias ideas. Sin embargo el carácter abstracto-formal de la mayoría de sus conceptos y argumentos es certificado por la presencia de una única ciencia social que debe dar sustancia a sus teorías: la teoría económica (ella misma muy abstracta y matématizada), y la casi falta de la psicología o sociología. Pero creo que de su teoría se pueden desprender unas consecuencias problemáticas, también por el lado práctico de los problemas. Por ejemplo podemos remarcar que la imagen global del Estado minimal contrasta fuertemente con el funcionamiento y las características del Estado capitalista contemporáneo. Aquí podemos tomar en cuenta una observación de Gray: “En la explicación de 8 UNA VISIÓN COMPARATIVA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA JUSTICIA 31 Nozick el Estado existe únicamente para proteger los derechos lockeanos que poseen los hombres en el estado de naturaleza. Entre estos derechos se encuentra un derecho inviolable a la propiedad — violado por la imposición fiscal sobre los ingresos, que Nozick caracteriza como algo semejante al trabajo forzado. ¿Cómo ha de financiarse, entonces, el Estado mínimo? No por medios no coercitivos como el pago de servicios o loterías estatales, ya que, como señala el propio Nozick, estos lograrían recaudar los ingresos necesarios sólo si fueron monopolios e implicarían, por lo tanto, una violación de los derechos. De hecho la explicación de Nozick del Estado mínimo es insuficiente porque no contiene ninguna teoría de recaudación fiscal.”13 Otro problema es que si la teoría de la rectificación es aplicada a las situaciones concretas, entonces es más que cierto que el principio de la rectificación debe ser usado sobre la mayoría de los bienes y de las propiedades privadas existentes, porque casi todos fueron obtenidos claramente como resultado de unas injusticias. La inmensidad de ese proyecto muestra lo utópico e inoperacional que es. Un mínimo realismo nos dice que esas cuestiones facticas son irreparables. Pero el mismo Nozick escribe, sólo una vez, que algunos acuerdos de asistencia social, incluyendo los de carácter altamente redistributivo pueden justificarse por su acción rectificadora de violaciones previas a la justicia liberal. En los últimos años Nozick ha reanalizado sus planteamientos, y su imagen sobre la vida de los individuos y sobre el ser social parece ser diferente, porque la antigua visión no tenia cuenta de la importancia simbólica de las preocupaciones y acciones políticas con carácter oficial en el dominio de los problemas sociales de interés mutuo que la gente quiere resolver. Vamos a analizar ahora una visión un poco diferente: la visión de Phillipe Pettit, una teoría que se inscribe en una tradición secular de Machiavello hasta Hannah Arendt en nuestro siglo. Para comenzar voy a analizar unos planteamientos generales de la teoría republicana, y después me voy a enfocar sobre su concepción de la igualdad y comunidad. Para caracterizar la tradición republicana vamos a usar las palabras de Pettit: “La tradición republicana no es intrínsecamente populista, y no es particularmente comunitarista. La libertad republicana es un ideal comunitario, en el sentido que se verá en el Capitulo 4, pero el ideal es compatible con formas de sociedad modernas y pluralistas. Y aun cuando la tradición republicana halla valiosa e importante la participación democrática, no la considera un valor básico inconmovible. La participación democrática puede ser esencial para la republica, pero sólo porque resulta necesaria para promover el disfrute de la libertad como no-dominación, no por sus atractivos intrínsecos: no porque la libertad, según sugeriría una concepción positiva, no sea ni más ni menos que el derecho a la participación democrática.”14 En la teoría republicana, en contrasto con la imagen populista del Estado que representa al pueblo como amo y al Estado como siervo, el pueblo es visto como fideicomitente y el Estado como fiduciario. Una concepción muy interesante de Pettit es su concepción de la libertad. Usualmente existen dos concepciones de la libertad: una negativa — la libertad 9 RÃZVAN PANTELIMON 32 como no-interferencia y una positiva — la libertad como autocontrol. Pero Pettit va a construir una tercera posibilidad que es la concepción de la libertad como no-dominación, que “exige que nadie sea capaz de interferir arbitrariamente en las elecciones de la persona libre”.15 Y eso fue también la concepción de la libertad que abrazó la larga tradición republicana. Esta no-dominación es vista como “una ausencia de dominación en presencia de otra gente: se trata de un ideal social que exige que, existiendo otra gente que podría ser capaz de interferir arbitrariamente en la vida de la persona en cuestión, esas personas se vean impedidas de hacerlo”.16 Para promover y guardar dicha no-dominación en una sociedad, hay dos posibilidades: todos llegan a tener iguales poderes, o sea un régimen jurídico que frene las ansias de dominación de la gente, sin convertirse él mismo en una fuerza de dominación. La libertad como no-dominación tiene grados tanto de intensidad, cuanto de alcance. Puede incrementar su intensidad, en la medida en que se reducen los factores comprometedores de la libertad — las presencias dominadoras que hacen ilibre a la gente — o puede incrementar su alcance, en la medida en que disminuyen las influencias condicionantes — las limitaciones naturales, culturales y jurídicas, que hacen a la gente no ilibre, pero sí no-libre. Si pensamos en la no-dominación como ideal político, su mayor atractivo viene del hecho de que “su maximización exige la promoción de tres beneficios, que la mera maximización de la no-interferencia podría pasar por alto: la ausencia de incertidumbre, la ausencia de necesidad de deferencia estratégica frente a los poderosos y la ausencia de subordinación social a otros”.17 La conexión entre la libertad como no-dominación y estos beneficios es tal, que esta libertad es un bien primario, en el sentido de John Rawls; es algo que la gente tiene razones para desear, con independencia del resto de sus deseos. Pero ese tipo de libertad no es el tipo de bien cuya persecución pueda dejarse en las manos de la gente para que lo persigan por sí mismas de manera particular, todo indica que lo mejor es perseguirlo para cada uno mediante la acción política de todos: perseguirlo por vía estatal. Antes hemos visto dos puntos de vista sobre la justicia y la igualdad en las obras de Rawls y Nozick, ahora me voy enfocar sobre la propuesta de Pettit en lo relativo al problema de la igualdad en el Capitulo 4 de su libro. Inicialmente critica las propuestas de los utilitaristas y de los adeptos de la libertad como nointerferencia, porque resultan desigualdades. “Eso lo reconocen implícitamente los devotos de la libertad como no-interferencia (Rawls), que insisten en que el objetivo no es tanto la libertad como tal, cuanto la igual libertad. No hay forma, compatible con la lógica, de maximizar el disfrute de igual libertad, sin distribuir la libertad en medidas iguales, cautela que tiene por efecto convertir la nointerferencia en un objetivo igualitario.”18 En la visión de Pettit a diferencia de la libertad como no-interferencia y de la utilidad, la libertad como no-dominación revela una naturaleza considerablemente igualitaria, porque es extremadamente improbable que este tipo de libertad pueda ser maximizado con disposiciones como la del internamiento selectivo y de la subprotección selectiva. 10 UNA VISIÓN COMPARATIVA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA JUSTICIA 33 Un punto muy interesante de la teoría de Pettit es su distinción entre el igualitarismo material y lo que él denomina igualitarismo estructural. “Sostendré que un régimen republicano que trata de maximizar la no-dominación tiene que evitar iniciativas que toleren una desigual intensidad de no-dominación, pero no hay restricción alguna que impida tolerar el desigual alcance de la no-dominación, tolerar las desigualdades de recursos materiales. Sin estar obligado, pues, a abrazar un igualitarismo material, el consecuencialismo republicano está forzado a venir en apoyo de lo que llamaré un igualitarismo estructural. Puede haber muchas razones que lleven al republicanismo a tratar de reducir la desigualdad material, obvio es decirlo. Pero la conexión con el igualitarismo material no es tan expedita — no es tan independiente de contingencias empíricas — como la conexión con el igualitarismo estructural.”19 Para defender su idea de igualitarismo estructural Pettit parte de la idea que la intensidad de la libertad como no-dominación de que disfruta una persona en una sociedad esta en función tanto del poder de otros, como de su propio poder. El valor absoluto de la intensidad de no-dominación de que disfruta una persona está en función del valor relativo a los poderes: está en función de su tasa de poder en el conjunto de la sociedad. Por eso “cualquier iniciativa contraria a la igualdad contribuirá a que, al menos, dos partes sean menos iguales en su intensidad de no-dominación. Y contribuirá a ello, o bien incrementando los poderes de los poderosos o disminuyendolos de otra parte, o bien haciendo ambas cosas a la vez: en cualquier caso, empeorará la tasa de poder de la parte en desventaja”.20 Porque, como la intensidad absoluta de no-dominación de la parte débil está en función de sus poderes relativos, la iniciativa igualitaria no puede sino rebajarla. Aquí Pettit trae un argumento parecido a la teoría de maximin de Rawls: “una iniciativa antiigualitaria puede lograr la maximización de la intensidad esperada de no-dominación, sólo si las márgenes incrementales de la no-dominación esperada de los aventajados compensan las márgenes decrementales de la nodominación esperada de los desaventajados.” Y eso tiene como consecuencia que: “en el improbable caso de que partamos de una situación igualitaria en lo que todos disfrutaran de la misma intensidad de no-dominación, tendría poco o ningún sentido recurrir a iniciativas antiigualitarias con objeto de incrementar la intensidad global de la no-dominación disfrutada. Lo más probable es que esas iniciativas, al tiempo que redujeran la igualdad en la distribución de la no-dominación, reducirían también su intensidad global”.21 La conclusión de Pettit es en la misma línea: “El paso más prometedor es siempre el paso que contribuya a una mayor igualdad. […] el objetivo que nos proponemos al abrazar el ideal republicano de libertad es la promoción de una no-dominación igualmente intensa. Si tienen que mantenerse en substancias fieles a la tradición republicana, tendrán que hacer con la libertad como no-dominación lo que Rawls y muchos liberales hacen con la libertad como no-interferencia. Tendrán que convertir la igual libertad — estrictamente hablando, la libertad igualmente intensa — en su preocupación central. Por mi parte, yo no creo que ese paso resulte necesario, dado el carácter igualitario del valor fundamental.”22 11 RÃZVAN PANTELIMON 34 En lo que concierne el igualitarismo material, Pettit piensa que es posible que el nivel global de no-dominación en una sociedad se maximice en un punto en que algunos disfrutan de unas pociones no-dominadas de mayor alcance que otros, talvez porque trabajan con mayor empeño y tienen más recursos. Y por eso “no hay razón para pensar que por la vía de igualar los recursos, y de igualar el alcance de las opciones no-dominadas, el Estado pueda esperar maximizar el nivel global de no-dominación en la sociedad; aun suponiendo que sus iniciativas igualizadoras no cobren una forma dominadora, pueden traer consigo la imposición de más limitaciones que las que eliminan”.23 Para concluir podemos decir que aunque el proyecto republicano de promover la libertad como no-dominación implique la igual intensificación de la nodominación, no necesariamente entraña la igual extensión del alcance de las opciones no-dominadas. Aunque el proyecto sea comprometido con lo que hemos denominado igualitarismo estructural, no está esencialmente comprometido con ningún tipo de igualitarismo material. “Pueden ser razones para instituir ciertas igualdades materiales, pero se trata de razones más sujetas a contingencia empírica que las razones que venían en apoyo de la institución de la igualdad estructural: las razones para instituir la igualdad de intensidad con que la gente disfruta de la libertad como no-dominación.”24 NOTAS 1. John Rawls, Teoría de la Justicia, México– Madrid–Buenos Aires, Fondo de Cultura Económica, 1978, p. 84. 2. Ibidem, p. 82. 3. John Gray, Liberalismo, Madrid, Movimento Cultural Cristiano, 2000, p. 44. 4. John Rawls, op. cit., p. 171. 5. John Gray, op. cit., p. 45. 6. Robert Nozick, Anarquía, Estado y utopía, México DF., Fondo de Cultura Económica, 1978, p. 7. 7. Ibidem, p. 7. 8. Ibidem, p. 154. 9. Ibidem, p. 158. 10. Ibidem, p. 159. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. John Gray, op. cit., p. 50. Robert Nozick, op. cit., p. 170. John Gray, op. cit., p. 60. Phillipe Pettit, Republicanismo, Barcelona– Buenos Aires–México, Paidós, 1999, p. 25. Ibidem, p. 349. Ibidem, p. 351. Ibidem, p. 352. Ibidem, p. 151. Ibidem, p. 153. Ibidem, p. 154. Ibidem. Ibidem, pp. 157–158. Ibidem, p. 159. Ibidem, p. 160. POLITICAL SOCIOLOGY INVOCACIÓN DE MAX WEBER AL SONETO 102 DE SHAKESPEARE1 LUIS RENÉ ORO TAPIA Este ensayo tiene por propósito identificar y explicitar cuáles son las ideas que subyacen tras las imágenes que Max Weber utiliza para configurar su concepción de la vocación política. Cuando Weber trata de esbozar tal noción, en las últimas líneas de su conferencia Politik als Beruf, lo hace mediante un lenguaje que es altamente estético y críptico a la vez. Atendiendo a tal peculiaridad este artículo intenta, en la medida de lo posible, convertir las metáforas en conceptos. Ello, con la finalidad práctica de ayudar al lector de Politik als Beruf a rescatar el sentido del mensaje que Weber quiso transmitir a sus interlocutores. Si este ensayo alcanza su objetivo, será a costa de deslucir la plasticidad de las imágenes de las que se sirve el profesor de Munich para delinear sus planteamientos. Contexto y Texto ¿Qué sentido tiene citar un poema de amor en un discurso que tiene por tema principal la política? Más aún, ¿cuál es la pertinencia de un soneto que alude al canto del ruiseñor, a la primavera y la alborada del estío en un contexto en que se habla del Estado, la violencia y el carácter demoníaco del poder? El texto es una partícula del contexto. Por eso, para desentrañar el significado que tiene la segunda estrofa del soneto 102 de Shakespeare en la conferencia Politik als Beruf de Max Weber2, es preciso aludir aunque sea brevemente al ambiente en el que ella fue dictada. Max Weber pronunció dicha conferencia aproximadamente ochenta días después del término de la Primera Guerra Mundial. Alemania, como se sabe, perdió la guerra. Las tropas del Káiser Guillermo Il capitularon en las cercanías de Paris antes de que los ejércitos aliados ingresaran en suelo alemán. La derrota convirtió a los sacrificios realizados para ganar la guerra en penurias absurdas. Y no sólo la sangría demográfica (3,5 millones de jóvenes muertos), sino que además los esfuerzos económicos para financiar la contienda, el padecimiento de frío y hambre causado por la escasez de combustibles y alimentos y, en fin, todas las incomodidades suscitades por las restricciones en el uso de aquellos bienes que son indispensables en una incipiente civilización industrial. Toda guerra en términos humanos es un desastre, pero lo es mucho más aún para quienes son derrotados. Cuando los vencidos se sienten defraudados por la conducción de la guerra exigen explicaciones a sus líderes y, si los resultados Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 35–42, Bucharest, 2005. 36 LUIS RENÉ ORO TAPIA 2 son inexplicablemente adversos, no sólo buscan responsables sino que además culpables. En Alemania el sindicado fue el Káiser. Por eso, la derrota contribuyó a poner fin a la monarquía y su derrumbe suscitó un vacío de poder, con su respectiva crisis de gobernabilidad. Ésta pronto devino en “revolución”. La sociedad alemana estaba divida y se revolvía contra sí misma. Ello dio pie a acusaciones y recriminaciones recíprocas, las que junto a otras variables políticas atizaron la discordia hasta llevarla al umbral de la guerra civil. Alemania comenzó a vivir un momento crepuscular. Para unos era el crepúsculo del amanecer, para otros, en cambio, el del atardecer. Así, lo que estaba en ciernes podía ser el luminoso comienzo de una nueva era o, por el contrario, un naufragio nocturno en un mar bravío en una latitud en donde no se sabe si hay tierra firme cerca. En tales circunstancias todo parece, paradojalmente, posible e imposible a la vez. En ellas se tiene la sensación de que todo está por hacerse y de que es factible de realizarse o, inversamente, que ya no hay nada más que hacer, excepto conservar y defender a ultranza lo poco que va quedando. Un protagonista crucial de ese tiempo crepuscular fue la juventud. Pero ella distaba de constituir un actor político unitario. Ella, en efecto, no estaba cohesionada en torno a una figura política indiscutida ni conformaba un grupo ideológicamente homogéneo. En ella había sectores anarquistas, nacionalistas, comunistas y pacifistas cristianos y seculares. Ellos constituyen el grueso del público que asiste a la conferencia de Weber. Pero no obstante su heterogeneidad tienen algo en común: participan activamente en los acontecimientos políticos que están en marcha y se sienten auténticos políticos de vocación, en cuanto dicen tener o creen tener vocación para la política. En seguida transcribiré el soneto 102 completo.3 La estrofa que cita Weber la pondré cursiva. La traducción que aquí ocupo es ligeramente diferente de la que aparece en las diversas ediciones en español de Politik als Beruf. En ellas los traductores tratan de conservar el número de sílabas de cada verso, al costo de forzar el mensaje del poeta. En cambio, la traducción que transcribo más abajo es más libre en cuanto al “metro”, pero se ciñe más al mensaje que quiere transmitir el hablante lírico. Mi amor es más fuerte, aunque más débil en apariencia; no amo menos, aunque parezca que amo menos. Es amor mercantilizado el que es pregonado a toda voz por su poseedor. Nuestro amor era lozano y primaveral, cuando yo acostumbraba a celebrarlo con mis rimas, pero ahora es como el del canto del ruiseñor al acercarse el estío que termina por apagarse al avanzar los días maduros. No es que el estío sea ahora menos apacible que cuando sus hermosos himnos hacían callar la noche, pero ya discorde rebalsa de todas las ramas la música, y las cosas dulces, al vulgarizarse, pierden su apreciado deleite. Así como él yo guardo mi flauta porque no quiero seguir ajando vuestra alegría con mi canto. 3 INVOCACIÓN DE MAX WEBER AL SONETO 102 DE SHAKESPEARE Amor y Política 37 El motivo del soneto es el amor. En él se contrapone el ímpetu del amor juvenil a la serenidad del amor maduro. Weber al apropiarse del soneto retransmite el mensaje del hablante lírico a los jóvenes, pero en clave política. Así, el motivo del soneto ya no es el amor erótico, sino que ahora es la política. En efecto, el destinatario del mensaje ya no es una pareja de jóvenes que disfruta de la embriaguez del deleite amoroso, sino que ahora se trata de la fascinación que la juventud siente por la política. En ambos casos se trata de la embriaguez, fascinación y arrobamiento que suscita el objeto amado. Y en ambos casos los sujetos que experimentan intensamente las pasiones son personas jóvenes. A partir de tales similitudes se puede establecer un paralelo entre el ímpetu amoroso y el entusiasmo por la política. Así establecida la ecuación, queda claro, entonces, que los destinatarios inmediatos del mensaje son los jóvenes que proclaman tener, o que creen tener, vocación para la política, en cuanto se sienten fascinados, atraídos o encantados por ella. La pregunta que implícitamente está haciendo Weber a los jóvenes es si la pasión que sienten por sus respectivas amadas es de similar índole a la pasión que sienten por la política. Si la respuesta a esta pregunta es afirmativa surgen otras interrogantes. En primer lungar, ¿si la continuidad de una actitud está garantizada por el sólo hecho de sentir intensamente una emoción en un momento dado? Y ésta remite a otra, ¿qué tan estables son los sentimientos? El llamado de Weber es a no confundir el enamoramiento con el amor. Uno es intenso, abrasador y fugaz. El otro recatado, apacible y duradero. Quienes están más expuestos a incurrir en tal indistinción son los jóvenes que experimentan pasiones intensas, pero evanescentes. El ímpetu de ellas los induce a sobrestimar la magnitud y consistencia de sus sentimientos y simultáneamente los impulsa a realizar actos temerarios de los que después son reacios a hacerse responsables. Así como es necesario distinguir el enamoramiento del amor, análogamente es indispensable distinguir el entusiasmo de la vocación. ¿Qué es la vocación? Como punto de partida hay que señalar que la vocación es algo más que un estado de ánimo que predispone favorablemente a realizar un determinado tipo de quehacer. En efecto, es algo más que un entusiasmo pasajero por aquello que resulta atrayente. La vocación es una motivación persistente en el tiempo, en cuanto permanece lozana a pesar del paso de los años. Ella, por cierto, no se marchita con las vicisitudes de la vida, ni es mutilada por los vaivenes anímicos, ni es amagada fácilmente por la adversidad. En el primer verso que está en cursiva se habla de un amor idealizado que se perpetúa en una eterna primavera, que se traduce en un perenne bienestar. En él no se hace alusión a los días difíciles y menos aún a la manera de cómo afrontarlos cuando ellos sobrevengan. El llamado de Weber es a evitar ver la realidad a través de un visillo de idealizaciones y ensoñaciones. Es una invitación a abandonar el romanticismo político. No hay correspondencia entre la vida política real, menos aún en una situación revolucionaria que por definición es violenta, y el lugar apacible que describe el soneto. En el segundo verso (en 38 LUIS RENÉ ORO TAPIA 4 cursiva) se refiere a la celebración de la situación descrita en el verso anterior, que análogamente corresponde a la exaltación del proceso revolucionario, a la euforia que produce la pasión política que ha suscitado “este carnaval al que se le embellece con el orgulloso nombre de revolución”.4 La vida política no tiene nada de poética. Menos aún durante un proceso revolucionario. Las revoluciones no estallan en lugares apacibles ni en sociedades donde reina el amor. Por eso Weber, con cierto dejo de ironía, advierte a los jóvenes que se sienten arrebatados por el ímpetu revolucionario que “sería muy bello que las cosas fueran de tal modo que se pudiera aplicar el soneto 102 de Shakespeare”.5 Sin embargo la vida real dista del talante anímico que trasunta el soneto. Más aún durante el transcurso de una revolución, pues en ellas las relaciones humanas se tornan más tensas y abrasivas e incluso violentas. Mientras ella dure, la violencia permanece al acecho y la irrupción de ésta puede traer consigo devastación, sufrimiento y muerte. En efecto, “lo que hay fuera” — en la calle, en la manifestación, en la barricada — es una realidad diferente de la que esboza el soneto. La política tiene sus cuotas de incertidumbre y ciertas dosis de coerción y antagonismo. Ellas aumentan su intensidad durante una revolución. Así por ejemplo el antagonismo verbal deviene en conflicto existencial, con lo cual la palabra es reemplazada por la fuerza y el espacio del antagonismo se traslada de la tribuna a la calle. En efecto, las luchas callejeras entre las facciones en pugna ponen en riesgo la vida de los antagonistas y si la intensidad del conflicto sigue creciendo puede alcanzar el umbral de la guerra civil. Así, el quehacer político cuando está impregnado de tensiones y antagonismos se asemeja más a la frialdad de una noche polar que cobra sus víctimas que a la apacible calidez de una mañana primaveral. La actividad política no tiene nada de poética en el sentido estético del término. En conclusión, Weber quiere establecer un contrapunto entre la realidad que describe el soneto, especialmente en sus dos primeras líneas, y el mundo externo. Incita a los jóvenes a admitir las circunstancias concretas en las que ellos están insertos: un país devastado, una revolución en marcha y un futuro incierto. En ella no hay primaveras ni trinos de aves mañaneras. Por el contrario, más bien parece estar incubándose el advenimiento de una noche polar. Desengaños y Política Weber no pretende sugerir a los jóvenes que dejen de soñar. Su mensaje es otro: que lo hagan, pero sin perder de vista la realidad factual. Más aún, los insta a perseverar en sus sueños. Con tal propósito les recuerda que la historia demuestra que no se hubiese alcanzado lo posible si no se hubiese intentando una y otra vez lo imposible.6 Sin embargo, quien quiera proponer ideales de perfección primero debe mirar al mundo tal cual es y al hombre en su desnuda realidad, con sus potencialidades y debilidades, porque solamente atendiendo a ellas se pueden elaborar ideales que sean factibles de materializar. Si algunos intentos por cambiar el mundo efectivamente han tenido éxito se debe a que quienes los llevaron a cabo estaban conscientes de las peculiaridades de la materia con la que operaban y supieron en qué momento actuar. Si pudieron 5 INVOCACIÓN DE MAX WEBER AL SONETO 102 DE SHAKESPEARE 39 alcanzar sus metas fue porque persistieron en su empeño, actuaron de manera prudente y conocían a cabalidad los recovecos del alma humana. Por cierto, disponían de vocación, talento y sabiduría. La primera incita a perseverar en las metas que se quieren alcanzar; el segundo sugiere de manera prudente los cursos de acción a seguir; la tercera brinda un conocimiento razonable de orden práctico. La conjunción de tales cualidades permite incrementar las probabilidades de tener éxito en el mundo de la política. Entendido éste como el logro de los fines. Tales exigencias y complejidades quedan en evidencia cuando Weber les recuerda a los jóvenes que “la política consiste en horadar lenta y profundamente unas tablas duras con pasión y distanciamiento al mismo tiempo”.7 En efecto, para alcanzar las metas, y así el éxito, es necesario saber de qué fibra, de qué madera, está hecho el hombre que es la materia sobre la que se opera. También es necesario no cejar frente a la adversidad, ni dejarse amilanar por las dificultades y la magnitud de las tareas a realizar. Asimismo se debe tomar distancia de la pasión puesto que obnubila a la razón, pero teniendo el cuidado de que permanezca siempre viva, porque ella es el motor de la acción. Si ella se extingue muere la vocación y sobreviene el desgano, la apatía y el inmovilismo. Sin embargo se corre el riesgo de que la persistencia se transforme en tozudez. El empecinamiento que ésta suscita, al no poner reparo en los efectos colaterales que genera, puede terminar desacreditando las metas que ella misma quiere alcanzar. Para evitar tal estropicio, la persistencia debe estar asistida por la prudencia. Ésta es quien determina en qué momento es oportuno actuar y discierne sobre la pertinencia de los medios que se deben emplear para insistir, una vez más, en el fin que se pretende alcanzar. La elección de los medios es clave, porque si ellos no son los adecuados se puede poner en riesgo la existencia misma del ideal en cuanto tal. Por cierto, se debe evitar que los medios desacrediten, difamen e incluso lesionen gravemente el prestigio del ideal que se desea implementar.8 ¿Cómo van a reaccionar los jóvenes, en el ocaso de la primavera, cuando tengan las primeras sospechas de que la política es un conflicto de intereses que se disfraza como lucha de principios? Al final del verano, cuando ya estén cayendo las primeras hojas, comenzará a escucharse el inquientante palpitar de la verdad fáctica que se oculta atras el follaje semántico. Ella con su muda presencia interpelará la retórica de los políticos que dicen actuar inspirados por valores sublimes. Es el momento en que comienza a insinuarse el rostro duro de la realidad y su acceptación o rechazo constituye la prueba de fuego para discernir si alguien tiene vocación para la política o no. Es la hora del despertar atónito, del parpadear incrédulo y del preludio que anuncia el ocaso de las ensoñaciones. Ese preludio es como el canto del ruiseñor al acercarse el estío que termina por apagarse al avanzar los días maduros. Esta imagen del derrumbe de las ilusiones y del declive del brío estival, de la armonía bucólica orquestada por el ruiseñor, dará paso a una realidad grisácea que no tardará en tornarse macilenta y en suscitar una sensación de desconsuelo aun en el alma de los más optimistas. ¿Qué sucederá cuando despunte el alba, cuando haya quedado atrás la magia de la noche, y la luz matinal permita ver claramente el contorno y el dintorno de las cosas? Cuál irá a ser nuestra actitud cuando dejemos atrás las ensoñaciones 40 LUIS RENÉ ORO TAPIA 6 nocturnas y observemos la realidad a plena luz del día, ¿cambiaremos nuestro juicio acerca de la realidad? ¿Aceptaremos la realidad con sus testarudas imperfecciones o insistiremos en seguir viéndola como algo potencialmente bello y perfectible? ¿Intentaremos cambiarla o renegaremos de nuestros ideales de la noche anterior? ¿Qué sentimentos irán a experimentar los jóvenes entusiastas en las últimas horas del día al final del verano? ¿Sentirán nostalgia por lo que se fue y no volverá? ¿Se quederán con sus miradas ancladas en el pasado? Si las respuestas a estas interrogantes son afirmativas, es porque fueron incapaces de asumir la realidad en su cotidianidad, tal cual ella es. Al negarse a aceptarla se evaden de ella. ¿A dónde? Hacia el pasado o el futuro. Y tal huida los incita a refugiarse en idealizaciones, creando así mundos de fantasía acorde a sus ensoñaciones. En el fondo, entonces, carecían de la fuerza de voluntad y la dureza de alma necesaria para sobreponerse a los continuos desencantos y frustraciones que suscita la lucha politíca.9 Por consiguiente, habría que sacar la conclusión de que no tenían vocación para la política. De Pie en Medio de las Ruinas La política gradualmente comienza a perder su encanto y a causa de ello van desapareciendo los políticos que viven para ella y no de ella. Los escasos hombres que ingresan a la política guiados por nobles motivos pronto ven truncados sus sueños por el propio funcionamiento del campo de la política. Las entrañas de la política están hechas de asperezas, fricciones y resquemores y no todos los que a ella ingresan son capaces de afrontarlas sin costo alguno para sus ilusiones.10 La desilusión es un capítulo muy avanzado de la ilusión. Sólo puede sentirse desencantado de la política aquel que una vez se sintió encantado por ella. ¿Quiénes estarán menos expuestos a experimentar tales decepciones? Los que han nacido con los ojos abiertos. Ellos han asumido el mundo tal cual es, con todas sus asperezas, por consiguiente, no requieren de ideales acorde a sus ensoñaciones para cobijarse de sus inclemencias. Ellos pueden prescindir de los visillos románticos y mirar cara a cara la realidad sin sentir pavor, por eso son inmunes a los sortilegios que tienen por misión encantar el mundo y hacerlo más llevadero. Se suele decir que el paso de los años va amagando la capacidad de soñar y va apagando la sed de ideales. Pero no todos los hombres son iguales. También es posible encontrar ancianos soñadores. Quizás sería más justo decir que todos los hombres son ilusos y realistas al mismo tiempo. Sin embargo, ello no significa en modo alguno que todos sean igualmente ilusos o realistas en un mismo dominio de la realidad ni respecto a las mismas cosas al interior de ese dominio. Pero si existe algún dominio de la realidad en que es indispensable ser un realista, lo que en última instancia significa ser un perspicaz conocedor de la naturaleza humana, ese dominio es el de la política.11 La mayoría de las veces se trata de un conocimiento intuitivo o por connaturalidad que tienen algunos inviduos respecto de sus congéneres.12 Generalmente se trata de una aprehensión espontánea y profunda de un determinado segmento de la realidad.13 Por cierto, 7 INVOCACIÓN DE MAX WEBER AL SONETO 102 DE SHAKESPEARE 41 tal conocimiento rara vez se adquiere de manera teórica, sin embargo, tampoco está asociado invariablemente a la longevidad ni al haber tenido un determinado tipo de vivencias. La experiencia no implica necesariamente el haber vivido cierta cantidad de años. Sólo adquieren el estatus de experiencias aquellas vivencias que han sido previamente reflexionadas y asimiladas. Por cierto, el acta de nacimiento no garantiza por sí misma la posesión de la experiencia necesaria para evitar dejarse encandilar por el éxito ni para sobrellevar la adversidad con entereza. La experiencia, por el contrario, supone un cierto tipo de actitud que se caracteriza por “haber aprendido a mirar sin reservas las realidades de la vida y la capacidad para soportarlas y para estar interiormente a su altura”.14 Pero no todos los hombres están echos de la misma madera. Por eso Weber interpela a sus auditores15 y los invita a que imaginen que va a ser interiormente de cada uno de ellos cuando abran los ojos, cuando asuman la realidad factural. Por eso, desde el punto de vista humano, la pregunta sigue en pié ¿qué va a suceder con el optimismo de los jóvenes cuándo descubran que tras los “valores” se ocultan los intereses? Irá a ser ese el instante en que definitivamente se desvanecerán las ilusiones primaverales o por el contrario irá a ser el momento en que ellas se aquilaten. Si sucede esto último el calor del verano será su crisol y el frío invernal la fuente en la que serán templadas. Así, los jóvenes se trasmutaran en viejos. Pero la palabra “viejo” aquí significa ser poseedor de cierto temple de ánimo y éste no necesariamente supone tener una cifra abultada de años. Es la capacidad de mirar con desenfado al mundo, pero sin claudicar a él. Por eso Eduardo Ortiz dice con toda razón en mi opinión, que el realismo político es básicamente una actitud frente a la vida y el mundo.16 La vejez supone conocer los pliegues de la naturaleza humana, los laberintos del alma, las motivaciones, ambiciones y miedos ocultos que propulsan y direccionan el comportamiento de cada uno de nosotros. En tal sentido Maz Weber afirma — probablemente rescatando el tenor de las palabras que Dostoiewsky pone en boca de El Gran Inquisidor17 — que si “el demonio es viejo; haceros, pues, viejos para entenderlo”.18 El ruiseñor, como ave de la hora del crepúsculo, simboliza el despertar y el declive de una pasión; representa el paso del enamoramiento al amor; el tránsito del entusiasmo por la política a la genuina vocación política. Así la auténtica vocación política resulta ser ajena a los aspavientos, pues ella comienza a afianzarse en la medida que el ruiseñor va callando. Este es el sentido que tienen los cuatro primeros versos del soneto: Mi amor es más fuerte, aunque más débil en apariencia; no amo menos aunque parezca que amo menos. Es amor mercantilizado el que es pregonado/a toda voz por su poseedor. En efecto, el soneto relata metafóricamente una transición emocional, desde un ánimo alegre y optimista suscitado por el entusiasmo que generan las ilusiones políticas, hasta su posterior declive cuando ellas pierden su vigor y comienzan a desfallecer tras ser sobreexplotadas por la retórica sentimental. Ellas, finalmente, expiran a causa de la apatía, el hastío y la decepción. De hecho, el tedio deviene rápidamente en fastidio. Y es así como las cosas dulces al vulgarizarse pierden su apreciado deleite. Pero aquellos que permanecen inmunes, en lo esencial, a tal proceso de desvanecimiento 42 LUIS RENÉ ORO TAPIA 8 de los ideales, de evaporación de las ilusiones, y que son capaces de mantenerse de pie en medio de las ruinas y que pueden decir “dennoch, no obstante, a pesar de todo, sólo ésos tienen vocación para la política”19, concluye Weber.20 NOTAS 1. En memoria de los veteranos de los ochenta, de los setenta y de los sesenta. “¿Dó están? ¿Que se ficierón? ¿Fabrán desquijado los robustos leones? ¿A qué río fueron a parar” (Jorge Manriquez). 2. Existe casi una decena de traducciones de dicha conferencia al español. De ellas hay dos que sobresalen por su precision y claridad. Una es la de Francisco Rubio Llorente que lleva por rúbrica La política como vocación, y está incluida en el libro El político y el científico (Editorial Alianza, Madrid, 1967). La otra es la de Joaquín Abellán, publicada con el título La política como profesión (Editorial Espasa Calpe, Madrid, 1992). En esta minuta ocuparé la traducción de Joaquín Abellán, porque es la de más fácil acceso en nuestro medio. 3. Probablemente el soneto era parte del acervo cultural de la juventud de la época, o estaba de moda, cuando Weber pronunció su conferencia. De ser así, se puede presumir entonces que el auditorio lo conocía a cabalidad y en virtud de ello Weber se sirvió de él para aumentar la eficacia comunicativa del mensaje que intentaba transmitir. 4. Cf. Max Weber, La política como profesión, Madrid, Editorial Espasa Calpe, 1992, traducción por Joaquín Abellan, p. 145. 5. Ibidem, p. 163. 6. Ibidem, p. 164. 7. Ibidem, p. 164. 8. Un buen ejemplo de ello es la alusión que Weber realiza sobre las condiciones de paz leonina que se le impusieron a Alemania al término de la Primera Guerra Mundial. Al respecto sostiene que con el tiempo no quedará desacreditada la guerra sino que la paz como efectivamente después de hecho ocurrió. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 152. 9. Por cierto, la política no solamente es fuente de satisfacciones, sino que además de “continuas decepciones” y frustraciones. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 144. 10. La pregunta que Weber de manera implícita le realiza a los jóvenes es ¿si sus tiernos ideales en flor serán capaces de sobrevivir a los fríos de la otoñada? Por eso, les dice: “me gustaría saber qué ha sido interiormente de aquellos de ustedes que se sienten ahora como políticos de convicciones y que participan de la embriagues que significa esta revolución”. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 163. 11. Un político profesional — esto es, con vocación y talento a la vez — debe estar familiarizado con las sinuosidades de la naturaleza humana. El estadista, según Butterfield, debe “conocer a los seres humanos tal como verdaderamente son y entendérselas con ellos como tales”. Herbert Butterfield, Conflicto internacional en el siglo XX. Una visión cristiana, Buenos Aires, Ediciones Peuser, 1961, p. 23. También hay una reflexión similar en el trabajo de Eduardo Spranger titulado Formas de vida, Editorial Revista de Occidente, Madrid, 1966, p. 262 y siguientes. 12. Cf. Jorge Eduardo Rivera, De asombros y nostalgias. Ensayos filosóficos, Valparaíso, Ediciones de la Universidad de Playa Ancha, 1999, pag. 145 y siguientes. 13. Cf. Isaiah Berlin, El sentido de la realidad, Madrid, Editorial Taurus, 1998, p. 79 y siguientes. 14. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 162. 15. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 163. 16. Cf. Eduardo Ortiz, El estudio de las relaciones internacionales. FCE, Santiago de Chile, 2000, p. 100. 17. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 155. 18. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 161. 19. Cf. Max Weber, op. cit., p. 164. 20. Al momento de cerrar este artículo conviene recordar al lector el tenor de la apertura de la exposición de Weber: La conferencia que por deseos de ustedes he de pronunciar hoy les defraudará por diversas razones. Con tales palabras, en efecto, inició su intervención. En ellas hay una advertencia: la conferencia defraudará. Los primeros decepcionados serán aquellos que esperaban oír palabras dulzonas del maestro. La conferencia, por el contrario, es de un realismo descarnado. ¿Por qué habrá optado por tal enfoque? Personalmente, creo que lo hizo para incitar a sus oyentes a asumir con responsabilidad el juego de la política. Por tal motivo, es indispensable que aquellos que se autodenominan políticos de convicciones acepten el carácter enrevesado y paradojal de la realidad factural. Pero si Weber insiste demasiado en ello corre el riesgo de amagar el idealismo de sus estudiantes. Entonces, ¿no será mejor que guarde silencio para evitar que se disipen las ilusiones restantes? Si opta por ello, su mutismo será como el del ruiseñor. En efecto, él — al igual que el ave mañanera — se abstendrá de enrostrar toda la verdad a los idealistas por respeto a sus ilusiones. Por eso, invocando al ruiseñor, también pudo haber concluido su intervención con las últimas palabras del soneto: Así como él guardo mi flauta/porque no quiero seguir ajando vuestra alegría con mi canto. IDEA DI NAZIONE E QUESTIONE DELLE NAZIONALITÀ NEL PENSIERO DI GIUSEPPE MAZZINI FRANCESCO GUIDA Nell’affrontare una ricerca sull’influenza che il pensiero e l’azione politica di Mazzini ebbero in diversi Paesi europei ed extraeuropei è facile correre il rischio di amplificare ciò che è di scarsa importanza, di dare corpo alle ombre e deformare la realtà storica. A volte, nel leggere i saggi dei numerosi collaboratori che hanno parlato in particolare del problema delle nazionalità e dell’influenza mazziniana sulle singole rinascite nazionali, la sensazione è appunto che qualcuno abbia forzato la mano ai fatti o che abbia scritto pagine dettate da eccessivo entusiasmo. Il compito di questa relazione, ma anche del nostro intero colloquio scientifico è proprio di ridurre l’impressionante massa di materiali frutto della ricerca di decine di studiosi al minimo comune denominatore della credibilità scientifica. Il dibattito sulle singole relazioni senza dubbio fornirà un ulteriore contributo in tal senso. Non deve stupire che gli organizzatori (ai quali va il mio ringraziamento) abbiano scelto uno studioso di Storia dell’Europa orientale per trattare del problema delle nazionalità in seno a un convegno di studi dedicato a Giuseppe Mazzini. Credo non sfugga a nessuno che tale problema nodale per il Genovese, come per gli altri osservatori del tempo, nonché per gli studiosi in seguito, riguardasse principalmente il continente europeo e in prevalenza la sua parte centro-orientale. Simile avvertimento venne da Angelo Tamborra1 già nel 1972 quando nel XXVI congresso di Storia del Risorgimento introdusse il gruppo di studio su Mazzini e l’Europa centro-orientale. Le vicende della zwischen Europa non esauriscono tuttavia la questione delle nazionalità, come provano ad esempio i saggi dei colleghi provenienti dalla Penisola iberica, Casassas e Ribeiro. Esse per restano al centro non solo dell’argomento, ma anche delle iniziative cospirative, propagandistiche e politiche dello stesso Mazzini attraverso più decenni. E se anche relazioni specifiche torneranno a trattare di questo, come ne trattano molti dei saggi la cui pubblicazione è stata già avviata dalla Domus mazziniana2, mi sia consentito di accennare qua e là nell’esposizione ad alcuni dei nessi esistenti tra pensiero e azione mazziniana, da una parte, e, dall’altra, le vicende della Polonia e dell’Ucraina, come dell’area danubiana o dei Balcani. Un primo quesito: il pensiero e l’azione di Mazzini influirono sull’esito delle vicende risorgimentali degli altri Paesi europei e in particolare dell’Europa Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 43–53, Bucharest, 2005. 44 FRANCESCO GUIDA 2 centro-orientale? Dalla comparazione degli avvenimenti occorsi nei più diversi Paesi e da quanto ci hanno saputo dire gli studiosi dovremmo concludere che influenza vi fu, ma restò limitata al campo dell’ideologia e delle idealità, solo in subordine attingendo quello della tattica e degli esiti politici. Ciò avvenne perché il messaggio mazziniano fu recepito con aggiustamenti e variazioni dettati dalle esigenze locali, ma anche e soprattutto perché l’indirizzo e la conclusione dei singoli movimenti risorgimentali vennero condizionati da numerosi altri fattori, sia interni sia (forse prevalentemente) esteri. Insomma l’equilibrio tra le potenze, l’azione delle diplomazie, gli interessi economici pesavano sulla bilancia ancor più dei principi mazziniani, incluso lo stesso principio di nazionalità, fatto proprio da parte di tanti che mazziniani non erano, compresi gli uomini di governo. E’paradossale che la narodnost’ sia (con la samoderzavie e la pravoslavie) uno dei punti del programma ideologico preparato dal ministro Uvarov per lo zar Nicola I, il vero “gendarme d’Europa”. Già molti anni fa Jože Pirjevec (allora firmava ancora Giuseppe Pierazzi) aveva individuato nei movimenti dei Giovani Sloveni e nei Giovani Boemi, come in alcuni esponenti del Risorgimento serbo e croato (anche di convinzioni per niente omogenee) coloro che ereditarono nel mondo slavo almeno parte dell’ideologia mazziniana. Di più, egli affermò che “la sua costante e ferma fiducia nella capacità dei popoli slavi di sollevarsi a dignità nazionale, il più valido legato che Mazzini abbia loro trasmesso”.3 Di più facile individuazione e di notevole peso la corrente mazziniana in senso al Risorgimento romeno, come gli studi di Delureanu4 hanno ripetutamente evidenziato e come la stampa romena lasciava trapelare anche in momenti non di massima libertà (e lo abbiamo letto in un saggio di Alberto Basciani).5 Frammenti di Mazzini troveremo persino in Tolstoi, mentre i saldi legami con i patrioti polacchi e ungheresi — al di là delle divergenze ora tattiche ora strategiche — non hanno neppure bisogno di essere ricordati.6 Dopo aver risposto a questo primo quesito, sia pure in forma approssimativa e riservandomi di aggiungere ancora qualcosa al riguardo un po’ più avanti, veniamo alle idee. Come è stato di recente ribadito autorevolmente da Salvo Mastellone7, il pensiero politico mazziniano si forma e si formula in maniera organica tra 1831 e 1848; gli anni successivi serviranno soprattutto a confermare la coerenza del personaggio, nonostante il mutare degli eventi, inclusa l’unificazione d’Italia che certo era il sogno che più gli stava a cuore. In questo processo di formazione ideologica, di progettazione giocata di continuo tra contingenza tattica e credo irrinunciabile, un grande ed essenziale spazio ebbe l’idea di nazionalità. Meglio sarebbe dire di nazione. Non spetta a me soffermarmi su di essa in modo ampio ed esauriente, ma è opportuno almeno ricordare che per il Genovese il cosmopolitismo di matrice illuministica settecentesca aveva attaccato e forse sconfitto una vecchia idea di nazione, di origine medievale; un’idea tutta legata alla figura del monarca o — nella migliore delle ipotesi — a una oligarchia nobiliare. Tale opera di demolizione era servita per esaltare i diritti fino allora conculcati dell’individuo: aveva insomma avuto una funzione positiva in una determinata epoca storica. Con il XIX secolo però si era aperta 3 IDEA DI NAZIONE N EL PENSIERO DI GIUSEPPE MAZZINI 45 una nuova epoca, che avrebbe avuto al suo centro non più l’individuo e la semplice libertà, bensì la nazione e la sua indipendenza (una più alta libertà) in opposizione agli imperi e al partito della “resistenza”, quindi all’ordine sancito nel congresso di Vienna, ma in armonia fraterna con le altre nazioni già formate o in formazione. Il passo successivo avrebbe visto tutte le crisalidi divenire farfalle e constituire insieme una grande unione, prima continentale, poi mondiale il che aveva un indubbio sapore millenaristico e mistico. Come il marxismo ha il socialismo, cioè la dittatura del proletariato, come fase ben intelligibile e criticabile, cui segue la più vaga epoca del comunismo, in cui si potrà fare a meno dello Stato, il mazzinianesimo propone la fase dell’affermazione delle patrie, delle nazioni di cittadini, concetto fruibile e applicabile almeno parzialmente nella realtà, per far seguire ad essa la meno concretizzabile realizzazione della piramide che vada dalla terra al cielo. Se questo punto di arrivo del pensiero mazziniano (passando per un governo democratico mondiale?) ci pare più vago e, tutto sommato, meno interessante, invece attrae tutta la nostra attenzione l’organamento di quel pensiero per la specifica fase dell’Ottocento, così come attrasse l’attenzione degli intellettuali dell’epoca, tanto all’Ovest quanto — e questo attiene maggiormente al mio intervento — all’Est. La nazione mazziniana doveva essere universale e democratica, non una natio nobiliare né il popolo di Berchet, borghesemente e orgogliosamente diverso dai molli parigini e dai selvaggi ottentotti.8 La nazione doveva essere composta da uomini che “formano un solo gruppo, riconoscono uno stesso principio, e si avviano, sotto la scorta d’un diritto comune, al conseguimento di un medesimo fine”.9 In presenza di masse contadine in Italia così come in tante altre regioni d’Europa l’universalità sembrava una generosa illusione, ma aveva in sé una carica attrattiva fortissima per chi agisse in nome di un interesse generale e non di classe o personale. A Mazzini non doveva sfuggire questo limite che potremo dire culturale, nel prefigurare una nazione di cittadini. Sapeva bene che le coscienze delle masse (spesso anche le conscienze dei ceti medi ed intellecttuali) non erano preparate e per questo insistette moltissimo per la loro educazione. Nei fatti tale opera si poté esercitare soltanto verso la classe operaia e in presenza di una forte concorrenza delle correnti socialiste, ma teoricamente essa doveva avere come destinatari tutti i futuri cittadini. Qui troviamo una congrueza del tutto spontanea tra l’opera mazziniana (non solo pensiero dunque come per il Genovese era norma costante) e la più remote esperienze di tardive rinascite nazionali. Penso alle biblioteche popolari e alle scuole serali da lui volute, che sembrano fare il paio con i čitaliste o gabinetti di lettura della Bulgaria. Lo scopo è semple lo stesso: formare la coscienza nazionale delle masse. Parallelamente l’invito lanciato durante l’esilio in Svizzera a credere nell’unità e a lavorare per essa, preparandole la via con il parlarne “au cultivateur, au paysan”10 ricorda fortemente l’andata al popolo dei populisti russi, anche se questi intendevano istruire le masse sui temi della giustizia sociale e del progresso civile, senza insistere sulla determinazione della coscienza nazionale. Ed eccoci in presenza di un nodo centrale del mazzinianesimo come delle diverse ideologie nazionali europee. Risorgimento è anche Nation-building. 46 FRANCESCO GUIDA 4 Certo non un’invenzione di intellecttuali o di mercanti attenti a construirsi un mercato più ampio e controllabile per le proprie merci (questo è solo un interesse che concorre alla crescita del consenso intorno alle correnti nazionali). Si construisce la nazione partendo da qualcosa che preesiste. Mazzini — e non è il solo — parla di riscoperta della nazione: la comunanza di lingua e di costumi, l’appartenenza alla stessa razza — insomma la nazione etnica — forniscono i mattoni per costruire la nazione in senso più nobile, la nazione “storica”. Un concetto di ben più ampio respiro, anche se di più difficile assimilazione: in esso, nella nazione “storica” possono rientrare elementi alloetnici. I vincoli che la storia comune crea, le comuni convinzioni democratiche, le regole che insieme i cittadini scelgono a suffragio universale sono la malta che lega i mattoni etnici. Un acuto osservatore della realtà odierna e del fenomeno secessionista o parasecessionista della Lega Nord, Gian Enrico Rusconi11 ha osservato non a caso che in esso scarso peso ha l’ethnos (peraltro di difficilissima identificazione), mentre si insiste molto sullo sfruttamento figlio del malgoverno centrale, romano e sulle capacità frustrate dei popoli del Nord (che se lasciati soli saprebbero governarsi molto meglio). Questo elemento che sembra accomunare Bossi a Mazzini naturalmente pesa molto meno di tutti gli altri che invece distinguono nettamente i due (ammesso e non concesso che una comparazione sia lecita sul piano intelletuale e morale). Per il Genovese se la nazione dei cittadini si costruisce, le sue basi sono già ben disegnate dai secoli: una nazione non si inventa dal niente; però se essa non è l’ethnos, non ne può prescindere, anche quando afferma (con atteggiamento che oggi potremmo definire antidarwinista): “nous ne croyons pas à l’eternité des races. Nous ne croyons pas à l’éternelle et tout puissante influence des climats sur le développement de l’activité humanitaire”. Infatti “la langue c’est le verbe d’un peuple; c’est sa pensée, l’idée qu’il est chargé de représenter dans le monde, le signe de sa mission”.12 Di più, un’insurrezione — egli lo ripete mille volte — che porti al successo della rivoluzione nazionale in una parte soltanto dell’Italia e, addirittura, dell’Europa, va contro il suo progetto politico, snaturandolo, sviandolo. Il Regno del Nord è per lui solo un piano dinastico dei Savoia, né si può pensare a liberare l’Italia (al congresso di Parigi del 1856 come nel convegno degli imperatori a Varsavia nel 1860 e nelle trattative diplomatiche degli anni Sessanta) a prezzo dei Principati danubiani da offrire come offa al molosso absburgico. Sia che guardi alla realtà nazionale italiana sia a quella europea resta per lui valida l’idea della rivoluzione sincrona e sinfonica — come diceva un uomo considerato forse a torto suo seguace, cioè Marco Antonio Canini.13 Mi pare particolarmente illuminante una considerazione di Mazzini a proposito della situazione spagnola dove non sembrava esistere un problema etno-nazionale, nonostante l’antica tradizione autonomista. “La révolution espagnole est bien une révolution nationale”14 — egli dice indirizzandosi agli uomini del “Propagador de la libertad” — perché opera la fusione del popolo, rende le genti “omogenee”. Par questa sua natura essa dovrà puntare all’umanitarismo mazziniano e non piuttosto al cosmopolitismo. Questo mira al trionfo dell’umanità attraverso l’individuo, l’umanitarismo attraverso la patria. E’ la stessa differenza che passa 5 IDEA DI NAZIONE N EL PENSIERO DI GIUSEPPE MAZZINI 47 tra semplice libertà piena, realizzata entro e attraverso l’associazione. Il cosmopolita rischia di restare passivo e non ottenere il suo scopo, oppure addirittura di accettare il dispotismo, confondendo fine e mezzi (i diritti individuali) e applicando l’egoistico ubi bene, ibi patria. Si osservi che il Genovese era contrario anche al cosmopolitismo dal basso, quello degli operai italiani all’estero che entravano in associazioni o sindicati stranieri e non italiani, sottraendo energie alla lotta patriottica, fase preliminare e imprescindibile per la vittoria dell’Umanità. Insomma, contrariamente a quello che venne critto nel Manifesto comunista, per il nostro i lavoratori avevano una patria. Curiosamente una tesi che di recente si ritrova in un intervento polemico di un acuto intelletuale di estrema sinistra, Luciano Canfora, il quale15 — parlando (si pensi un po’) della plutarchea Vita di Alcibiade — osservava che il vero internazionalismo apatriottico è da sempre quello classi agiate e dirigenti. Qui sembra opportuno ricordare anche un’osservazione di Marco Clementi sul recupero che del pensiero mazziniano si fece nella Russia di inizio Novecento (sottraendolo alla precedente censura) proprio in fuzione antisocialista. Dunque, proprio perché anche caso spagnolo vi è una patria in fieri, Mazzini può asupicare che di essa entri a far parte anche il Portogallo, nel contesto della Repubblica iberica. Tocchiamo così un altro punto dell’ideologia mazziniana che gli storici più volte hanno considerato con severità. La considerazione privilegiata nei confronti della nazione “storica”, cioè constituita liberamente attraverso una serie di eventi e scelte politiche, finisce talora per valere per la nazione storica tout court. Così vediamo il genovese accettare l’idea di una ricostituzione della Polonia quale era prima del 1772, cioè uno Stato sicuramente multietnico, comprendente elementi nazionali che avrebbero dovuto naturalmente scendere prima o poi. Più controverso il suo pensiero riguardo alla Corona magiara di Santo Stefano. Egli vorrebbe che una forte e vasta Ungheria continuasse a esistere quale maggior esponente di una Confederazione comprendente altri Stati. Di fronte alle resistenze di Kossuth e altri ungheresi a cedere alcuni territori storicamente, ma non enticamente magiari, si piega a riconoscere nel 1856: “La Transilvania dunque non sarà mai rumena? Non dico questo: credo anzi che la sarà. Ma credo che insistervi adesso sia fatale e impolitico.”16 Proprio questa frase poco in linea con il tono tranchant dell’oratoria mazziniana ci illustra chiaramente comme Mazzini fosse pienamente a giorno dei contrasti nazionali che impedivano una soddisfacente collaborazione tra le nazionalità oppresse. Egli non fece in tempo a vedere l’epoca di quello che ho definito una volta “irredentismo circolare” (io voglio liberare i miei compatrioti soggetti al tuo dominio, tu consideri irredenti i tuoi compatrioti sottomessi a un terzo e questi vuole unire al proprio Stato una minoranza compresa nel mio Stato), tipico dell’Europa centro-orientale; però conobbe bene e criticò il duro scontro tra nazionalità avvenuto nel biennio rivoluzionario 1848–49, scontro che giocò a tutto favore degli Absburgo e in genere delle potenze conservatrici. Contro quelle scelte controproducenti per le rivoluzioni nazionali egli cercò anzi di operare, non diversamente dai governanti piemontesi o dagli esuli polacchi radunati intorno a Czartoryski.17 Tutto fu vano e persino post res perditas, in 48 FRANCESCO GUIDA 6 attesa di una nuova più fortunata occasione, non gli riuscì di conciliare pienamente le avverse élites nazionali, per lo più riparate dalla propria terra. I progetti confederali successivi al 1849, in parte nuovi rispetto agli anni Trenta e Quaranta, restarono tutti sulla carta, sia per l’influenza determinante della politica internazionale dettata in genere dalle grandi capitali europee, sia per l’impossibilità di arrivare a un accordo generale tra le parti, per tutte soddisfacente. Lo stesso Mazzini peraltro, nel progettare Confederazioni atte a risolvere appunto i problemi connessi con la convivenza di diversi popoli nelle medesime regioni, commise alcuni errori. Quando, ad esempio, attribuziva alla nazione greca ampi territori abitati da popolazioni slave non si comportava diversamente da Napoleone I che alcuni decenni primi aveva parlato di sette milioni di greci18, sottovalutando uno dei problemi cruciali dell’equilibrio europeo del Novecento: parlo della Macedonia, centro della considdetta “polveriera d’Europa”. Non poteva imaginare che proprio in Macedonia si sarebbe dato il caso più eclatante di Nation-building, grazie a un pungo di pervicaci intelletuali19, alle divergenze serbo-bulgare e alle scelte politche, infine, di Tito. Sapeva per che anche nei Balcani stava privilegiando una nazione storica, la Grecia, che aveva avuto inoltre il merito di essersi risvegliata e ricostituita in Stato nazionale (benché incompleto) per prima. Erano anni in cui ancora non venivano percepite in Europa occidentale le prime avvisaglie di una rinascita bulgara (quella macedone non era neppure ipotizzabile, quella albanese non si era avviata concretamente e quella serba non era ancora collidente con il Risorgimento ellenico). Mi chiedo anche se egli fosse influenzato dal progetto confederale risalente addirittura al tardo Settecento del protomartire ellenico Rigas Fereos, il quale aveva immaginato uno Stato multietnico in cui la nazione greca avrebbe avuto un ruolo di prima inter pares e soprattutto di educatrice delle altre, più arretrate.20 Soltanto negli anni Sessanta e soprattutto con il noto incontro del 1869 con una delegazione dei Giovani bulgari (di recente ricordato dalle studiose Genova e Šarova21) la sua visione mutò, almeno in parte. Al di là di queste sbavature, è di grande importanza la convinzione mai venuta meno in Mazzini che la questione orientale fosse strettamente connessa a quella italiana, al punto che eventuali iniziative per risolvere una non dovevano e non potevano essere separate o indipendenti rispetto ad azioni per sciogliere l’altra. Gli eventi italiani del 1859 e soprattutto del 1860 era necessario, a suo parere, che trovassero un naturale seguito oltre Adriatico. Non era solo a pensarlo se Bixio a Cosenza arringò le camicie rosse come soldati europei e Garibaldi si farà coinvolgere in molteplici progetti lungo tutti gli anni Sessanta di sbarchi in Dalmazia o in Epiro, per colpire al cuore l’Austria o la Turchia e se persino il governo piemontese prima e italiano poi (per non dire della politica personale di Vittorio Emanuele II) coltivarono e sostennero idee del turro simili. Ma su questo capitolo di storia molto è stato scritto da Kerofilas a Maturi, da Tamborra a Liakos, da Koltay-Kastner a Caccamo22, ad altri ancora. Il nesso tra questione italiana e questione orientale non è solo dettato da esigenze tattiche nella lotta contro le potenze conservatrici. Vi è dietro una convinzione dottrinale. “Un peuple qui s’isole, est un peuple suicide”.23 Fare 7 IDEA DI NAZIONE N EL PENSIERO DI GIUSEPPE MAZZINI 49 politica estera è un obbligo morale di ogni nazione; non avere iniziativa internazionale significa essere soggiogato, averne in misura eccessiva non si armonizza con la missione della nazione. No, insomma, alla nazione-Arpagone ma anche e quella capitan Fracassa. Questi concetti furono suggeriti a Mazzini soprattutto dalla sua permanenza in Isvizzera. Egli che credeva che si potesse fare della Confederazione elvetica una vera, più ampia nazione (articolata lungo l’intero arco delle Alpi), condannava decisamente la sua tradizionale politica di neutralità, controprova di immaturità nazionale e, possiamo dire oggi a posteriori alla luce delle scoperte sull’oro trafugato dai nazisti, modo per difendre il proprio, anche più gretto interesse. Molto alto è anche il rifiuto della paura del panslavismo, cosi diffusa nell’Europa dell’Ottocento. Gli slavi non sono tutti legati ai “moscoviti”. Anche a voler tralasciare il clamoroso caso della grande ribelle, la Polonia (“tribu repoussée, et qui porte en son sein les germes d’un monde”)24, Mazzini è convinto che persino gli slavi balcanici o dell’Europa centrale i quali hanno manifestato simpatie per la politica russa verso l’impero ottomano, nutrono tale russofilia soltanto per ragioni tattiche. Essi saranno pronti a prendere in mano i propri destini quando gli altri popoli d’Europa li coadiuveranno in tal senso, dando inizio alle rivoluzioni nazionali. Lo stesso impero russo alberga in sé fermenti di grande importanza manifestatisi già con i decabristi e testimoniati dagli esuli come Herzen. Esso probabilmente finirà per dividersi in più parti, il giorno in cui fosse scosso dalla rivoluzione. Quanto scrive nel suo saggio Mykola Varvarcev25 sembra in parte confermare tale auspicio-previsione. Allora il grande mare slavo non costituirà più un impero aggressivo e in espansione, pericoloso per la libertà dell’intero continente europeo, bensì una grande confederazione di popoli liberi. E i grandi russi, il più numeroso popolo slavo orientale, volgeranno la loro opera alla civilizzazione dell’Asia. Qui il Genovese riprendeva un vecchio tema caro alla cultura europea: esso si ritrova a partire da quella controriformistica di un uomo che fece in parte la politica esteuropea dello Stato della Chiesa, il gesuita Antonio Possevino, il quale — sostenendo anch’egli fortemente la causa polacca — parla della Russia come “ponte lanciato verso l’Oriente”26, sino alle proposte che Molotov si senti fare a Berlino nell’autunno del 1940, di dirigere l’espansionismo sovietico verso il subcontinente asiatico. Se, dunque, questa sorta di invito rivolto ai russi di scegliere l’eurasismo (per usare una terminologia novecentesca) può lasciare forti dubbi, anche se l’impero zarista era di fatto una potenza distesa su due continenti, più fondato è il convincimento mazziniano che Pietroburgo e Mosca, lo zar e la Santa Sinodo non potessero condizionare ogni futuro gesto dei dirigenti dei popoli slavi occidentali e meridionali, ma che questi si sarebbero regolati di caso in caso secondo il proprio interesse. Mazzini non fece in tempo a vedere come si realizzasse a pieno la sua profezia a proposito del popolo che più dovette la propria liberazione alle armi russe, il bulgaro: già pochissimi anni dopo la nascita del Principato auatonomo di Bulgaria esso si mostrò estremamente ribelle agli intendimenti di Pietroburgo; uno dei protagonisti di quella ribellione, Stefan Stambolov, aveva mazziniamente ipotizzato una confederazione balcanica 50 FRANCESCO GUIDA 8 (Romania, Serbia e Bulgaria) forte a sufficienza per fare da sentinella alla Russia.27 Di nuovo la Bulgaria si schierò contro la Russia addirittura in guerra, al tempo del primo conflitto mondiale. Naturalmente ancora più clamoroso è il caso odierno dell’Ucraina, per estensione il secondo Paese del continente, gelosa della sua indipendenza pur in seno alla CSI, dopo essere uscita dall’URSS non soltanto per contestarne il regime totalitario, ma anche per motivazioni nazionali. L’ottimismo di Mazzini riguardo anche allo spauracchio panslavista non stupisce eccessivamente quando si ricordi la sua affermazione (questa si fondata su una visione troppo rosea) che “tous les membres de la famille européenne sont assez avancés pour être libres”.28 In modo del tutto parallelo egli credeva che anche il pangermanesimo poteva essere tenuto a bada proprio grazie a quella confederazione slava o centroeuropea che avrebbe reso non pericolosi i russi. Anche nella sua posizione rispetto al problema delle nazionalità, Mazzini — come si è già visto di sfuggita — non rimase immobile, pur in una coerenza di fondo. Cosi fu riguardo all’illirismo di Ludevit Gaj, dapprima non valutato come un fenomeno di grande significato, quando invece dovette accorgersi che esso, lavorando sul versante culturale, rafforzava il sentimento nazionale già vivo tra i croati, e allo stesso tempo preparava il terreno per l’incontro con l’altra importante nazione slavomeridionale, quella serba (che godeva di una semiindipendenza), sulla strada dello jugoslavismo.29 Si osservi che parliamo di una idea che, prima vincente poi sconfitta, ha avuto un ruolo importante nella storia europea del nostro secolo, di fatto costituendo l’unica concreta applicazione di quei progetti federali o confederali dello stesso Mazzini e di altri uomini dell’Ottocentro. Il lavoro culturale degli illiristi era in perfetta sintonia con un cardine del pensiero mazziniano: non basta l’indipendenza per avere la nazione. “Si l’amour de l’indépendance” — scrive Mazzini — pouvait être lui seul le principe de l’existence nationale, la moindre tribu du désert constituerait une nationalité”.30 Resta da dire più distesamente come presso i singoli popoli le idee mazziniane lasciarono il loro segno: non dappertuto la loro presa fu egualmente salda, anche se impressiona la loro diffusione. Di più, come capitò persino in Italia, quelle idee furono talora addomesticate oppure “selezionate”. Tra i croati esse furono tenute presenti da due uomini di opinioni del tutto diverse come Imbro Tkalac31 e Eugen Kvaternik, nonché più tardi da Frano Supilo. I già ricordati Giovani Cechi e Giovani Sloveni espunsero il credo essenziale dell’Austria delenda, influenzando anche altri giovani intellettuali slavo-meridionali. Al volger del secolo con il rafforzarsi delle tesi favorevoli alla rottura con Vienna e la costituzione di associazioni volte a porre fine al dominio austro-ungarico anche quel pilastro del progetto mazziniano venne recuperato. Lo testimonia l’esperienza della Giovine Bosnia che allineò gli uomini che compirono l’attentato di Sarajevo, organizzazione fortemente influenzata da letture mazziniane.32 Nel volume già apparso dedicato a “il Mazzinianesimo nel mondo” è illustrato molto chiaramente come l’influenza mazziniana anche in Ispagna, nazione già formata territorialmente prima dell’epoca dei Risorgimenti, andò mutando atraverso i decenni con il prevalere di tendenze più o meno radicali nel repubblicanesimo spagnolo.33 9 IDEA DI NAZIONE N EL PENSIERO DI GIUSEPPE MAZZINI 51 Naturalmente l’elenco potrebbe continuare. Già si è accennato al caso romeno in cui uomini (come i fratelli Brætianu o Rosetti)34 che rivestirono cariche ai massimi livelli politici furono schiettamente mazziniani o vicini a Mazzini nei suoi progetti di comitati o partiti transnazionali, che raccogliessero le forze democratiche dell’intero continente. I rapporti con Kossuth35 e con Mickiewicz sono tra le pagine più interessanti della vicenda mazziniana, come i suoi rapporti con altri esuli magiari e polacchi hanno fortemente caratterizzato per decenni le sue iniziative politiche. In particolare alcuni polacchi furono tra i suoi più fedeli seguaci, anzi suoi agenti in varie parti d’Europa.36 In alcuni casi questi interlocutori stranieri giocarono persino il ruolo di mediatori tra Mazzini e altri italiani; cito solo due esempi: la riconciliazione (peraltro effimera) con Garibaldi, favorita da Herzen37 e la mediazione di Klapka tra il Genovese e il re d’Italia.38 E’ idea piuttosto diffusa che nel pensiero mazziniano vi fossero i germi del nazionalismo anche deteriore: lo stesso Romeo39 autorevolmente era incline a crederlo, asserendo che il concetto di nazione di Mazzini non fosse solo di stampo francese o italiano, cioè che la nazione fosse essenzialmente una scelta, piuttosto che di matrice tedesca, cioè che la nazione fosse marcata da alcuni caratteri oggettivi indiscutibili (razza, lingua, territorio). Ho già detto la mia opinione all’inizio della relazione; aggiungo che si fa torto a Mazzini attribuendo a lui lo svilupparsi in senso negativo di potenzialità che nel suo pensiero avrebbe dovuto incanalarsi in tutt’altro senso. L’Europa centro-orientale sembra essere la più patente dimonstrazione di come la creazione-riscoperta delle nazioni e il loro costituirsi in Stato nazionale (cioè il nucleo stesso del mazzinianesimo) siano processi estremamente pericolosi che implicano necessariamente lo scontro — e non il mazziniano abbraccio — tra le nazioni dopo che esse si sono manifestate. Tra i suoi seguaci alcuni furono fautori di una Grande Croazia o di una Grande Serbia, o di uno Stato-nazione che si desse confini non più giustificabili nell’era delle nazionalità, dopo che lo erano stati in epoca medievale o moderna. Tuttavia proprio a un simile indesiderato evolversi del processo nazionale, Mazzini voleva ovviare con i progetti confederali, ma non solo. Se la nazione è una scelta e un sentire comune, lo strumento del suffragio liberamente espresso può effettivamente sciogliere in buona misura il grave, ancor attuale problema dei contrasti nazionali. Voglio citare un esempio: nel 1922 a Sopron la popolazione tedescofona optò per l’appartenenza allo Stato magiaro piuttosto che all’Austria, preferendo richiamarsi a vincoli tradizionali e storici piuttosto che a legami etnici.40 Sarebbe anche interessante oggi chiedere agli altoatesini se desiderano separarsi dall’Italia. Purtroppo molto raramente le popolazioni sono state libere di pronunciarsi sull’appartenenza a uno o a un altro Stato e a questo criterio non perfetto, ma sufficientemente sano e corretto, si è preferito quello dell’annessione per motivi di ordine militare, economico e quant’altro, oppure lo scambio delle popolazioni o, infine, la pulizia etnica, a tutti noi oggi ben nota. Qualcuno avrà già notato che sinora non ho toccato un altro campo in cui le iniziative di Mazzini facilmente hanno attirato le critiche degli storici. Mi riferisco alla teoria della guerra di popolo, alla fiducia nella forza del numero dei patrioti contro quella degli eserciti regolari. Credo che sia un tema su cui poco 52 FRANCESCO GUIDA 10 si possa aggiungere: effettivamente le azioni di bande armate dall’Italia alla Bulgaria non diedero mai grandi esiti con l’eccezione della spedizione dei Mille che però fa storia a sé per molti motivi. Proprio il suo successo restituì smalto alle tesi mazziniane riguardo alla guerriglia, forse confondendo un po’le acque. Il fenomeno infatti non si ripeté così come non ve ne era stato unor uguale nei decenni precedenti in nessun angolo del continente. Il dibattito sulla validità delle spedizioni di volontari proseguì ancora a lungo sino alle dure parole che il socialista Mussolini riservò a Ricciotti Garibaldi all’epoca delle guerre balcaniche.41 Resta assodato ce in assenza del concorso anche indiretto di un esercito amico la guerra di popolo aveva poche chances di successo. Proprio nel nostro secolo si è assistito tuttavia al fenomeno delle resistenze (anche di grandi dimensioni) che conseguirono spesso importanti successi, sempre per nel contesto di un conflitto più generale. Tanto è vero che le resistenze molto meno note del dopoguerra (in Ucraina e in Polonia contro il regime comunista) non ebbero esiti altrettanto positivi. Peraltro, al di là dell’affermazione puramente teorica di fede nella guerra di popolo, non bisogna dimenticare che, soprattutto negli anni Sessanta, Mazzini presupponeva che alcuni eserciti regolari (italiano, serbo, forse ungherese e polacco, o persino quelli inglese e francese) si muovessero all’unisono o almeno in conseguenza delle insurrezioni e delle spedizioni progettate dai Balcani alla Galizia. Il Genovese in quel torno di tempo — come è noto — non esitò a trattare con lo stesso re d’Italia. Spero di aver affrontato almeno i principali temi attinenti la forte relazione esistente tra la teoria mazziniana della nazione e le iniziative di Mazzini, da un lato, e le vicende delle nazionalità europee, principalmente esteuropee, dall’altro. Era, come si è visto, una relazione forte perché estremamente naturale, quasi scontata. Oso dire che se Mazzini fu un ideologo le cui idee furono comprensibili e condivisibili in qualsiasi Paese, in particolare il suo pensiero era adatto alla condizione di quei popoli che non avevano potuto ancora, nel secolo passato, realizzare un proprio Stato nazionale. Se egli non fosse esistito, quei popoli, che si trovavano al di qua ma ancor di più al di là dell’Elba, avrebbero dovuto cercare un altro iluminatore, un altro apostolo. NOTE 1. Angelo Tamborra, Introduzione al gruppo di studio su Mazzini e l’Europa orientale, in: “Mazzini e il mazzinianesimo”, Atti del XLVI congresso di Storia del Risorgimento, Roma, 1974, pp. 287–300. 2. Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, I–II, a cura di G. Limiti, Pisa, 1995–1996. 3. Giuseppe Pierazzi, Mazzini e gli slavi dell’Austria e della Turchia, ivi, p. 407. Questo saggio resta essenziale per la conoscenza delle relazioni ideali e materiali tra Mazzini e le diverse nazioni dell’Europa centro-orientale. 4. Ci limitiamo a citare ªtefan Delureanu, Mazzini e la Romania, ivi, pp. 413–479. 5. Alberto Basciani, Mazzini nella stampa romena dell’Ottocento, in: “Il Mazzinianesimo nel mondo”, I, cit., pp. 259–327. 6. Cfr. Marco Clementi, Mazzini, Tolstoj e Gandhi, in: “Rassegna Storica del Risorgimento”, LXXXVII, 2000, III, pp. 393–410. Dello stesso autore si veda Mazzini e la Russia, in: Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, I, cit., pp. 143–209. 7. Salvo Mastellone, Il progetto politico di Mazzini (Italia-Europa), Firenze, Olschki, 1994. 8. Giovanni Berchet, Sul ‘Cacciatore feroce’ e sulla ‘Eleonora’ di Goffredo Augusto Bürger, Lettera semiseria di Giovanni Grisostomo al suo figliuolo (1816): “Basti a te per ora di sapere che tutte le 11 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. IDEA DI NAZIONE N EL PENSIERO DI GIUSEP PE MAZZIN I presenti nazioni d’Europa (l’italiana anch’essa né più né meno) sono formate da tre classi d’individui: l’una di Ottentotti, l’una di Parigini; e l’una, per ultimo, che comprende tutti gli altri individui leggenti ed ascoltanti [...] A questi tutti io do nome di popolo.” Giuseppe Mazzini, Nazionalità. Qualche idea su una constituzione nazionale (1835), in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, VI, pp. 123–158. Idem, Nazionalità. Unitari e federalisti (1835), in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, VI, pp. 3–41. Gian Enrico Rusconi, Se cessiamo di essere una nazione. Tra etnodemocrazie regionali e cittadinanza europea, Bologna, Il Mulino, 1993. Giuseppe Mazzini, Humanité et patrie, in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, VII, pp. 201–218. Marco Antonio Canini, Vingt ans d’exil, Paris, 1868. Giuseppe Mazzini, De la nationalité au Propagador, in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, VI, pp. 331–351. Luciano Canfora, in: “Il Corriere della sera”, 1996. Giuseppe Mazzini, lettera a N. Fabruzi, 21 aprile 1856, in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, LVI, p. 192. Angelo Tamborra, Pasquale Fornaro, Risorgimento italiano e questione ungherese (1849–1867), Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino, 1995. Francesco Guida, Problemi del risveglio delle nazionalità balcaniche durante l’epoca napoleonica, in: Il risveglio delle nazionalità nel periodo napoleonico, Pisa, Giardini editori 1982, pp. 119–146. Marco Dogo, Lingua e nazionalità in Macedonia. Vicende e pensieri di profeti disarmati. 1902–1903, Milano, Jaca book, 1985. Rigas Fereos, La rivoluzione, la Grecia, i Balcani, a cura di L. Marcheselli, Trieste, Lint. 1999. Liudmila Genova, Krumka Šarova, Il movimento nazionale rivoluzionario bulgaro e le idee di Mazzini, in: Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, II. Costas Kerofilas, La Grecia e l’Italia nel Rosorgimento italiano, Firenze, La Voce, 1919; Domenico Caccamo, Angelo Tamborra, Garibaldi e l’Europa, Roma, SME; Antonis Liakos, L’unificazione italiana e la Grande idea. Ideologia e azione dei movimenti nazionali in Italia e in Grecia, 1859–1871, Firenze, Aletheia, 1995. Giuseppe Mazzini, Nazionalità. Qualche idea su una constituzione nazionale (1835), in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, VI, p. 127. Idem, Un mot sur la question polonaise, in: “Scritti editi e inediti”, VII, p. 232. Mykola Varvarcev, Mazzini e l’Ucraina nell’Ottocento, in: Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, II. 53 26. Francesco Guida, Antonio Possevino e la Livonia: un episodio della Controriforma (1582–1585), in: “Europa orientalis”, II, 1983, pp. 73–105; Idem, Ivan il Terribile e Antonio Possevino: il difficile dialogo tra Cattolicesimo e Ortodossia, in: Le origini e lo sviluppo della Cristianità slavo-bizantina: il battesimo del 988 nella lunga durata, Roma 1992, pp. 261–275. 27. Idem, Nascita di uno Stato balcanico. La Bulgaria di Alessandro di Battenberg nella corrispondenza diplomatica italiana (1879–1886), Napoli, Edizioni scientifiche italiane, 1988, 508 p. (con A. Pitassio e R. Tolomeo). 28. Giuseppe Mazzini, Nationalité et propagande, in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, XII, pp. 252–257. 29. Giuseppe Pierazzi, loc. cit. 30. Giuseppe Mazzini, Nazionalità. Qualche idea su una costituzione nazionale, in: “Edizione nazionale degli scritti”, VI, 1835, p. 150. 31. Angelo Tamborra, loc. cit. 32. Giuseppe Pierazzi, loc. cit., p. 412. 33. Jordi Casassas, Albert Ghanime, Josep Pich, Teresa Abellò, La influencia de Mazzini en el republicanismo español, in: Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, I, cit. pp. 77–142; Isabel Pascual Sastre, Mazzini y los republicanos españoles, in: Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, II, cit. 34. ªtefan Delureanu, loc. cit. 35. Koltay Kastner. 36. Giuseppe Monsagrati Tomassucci, Mazzini e la Polonia “sorella combattente”, in: Il mazzinianesimo nel mondo, II. cit. 37. Fu Aleksandr Herzen a descrivere l’incontro tra i due più noti esponenti del Risorgimento italiano in casa sua a Londra, nelle pagine oggi raccolte nella Polnoe sobranie socinenie, Moskva, Nauka; ma anche la breve antologia Aleksandr Herzen (episodio intitolato Camicia rossa), Mazzini e Garibaldi, Roma e/o, 1955. 38. Giuseppe Pierazzi, loc. cit., p. 382. 39. Lo nota Gennaro Sasso, Rosario Romeo e l’idea di “nazione”. Appunti e considerazioni, in: Il rinnovamento della storiografia politica. Studi in memoria di Rosario Romeo, Roma, Istituto dell’Enciclopedia Treccani, in particolare p. 126. 40. Marta Petricioli, La questione dell, Ungheria occidentale nei documenti diplomatici italiani, in: Italia e Ungheria (1920–1960). Storia, politica, società, forti, a cura di F. Guida e R. Tolomeo, Consenza, Periferia, 1991, pp. 1–30. 41. Saint Jorios, Francesco Guida, Ricciotti Garibaldi e il movimento nazionale albanese, in: “Archivio storico italiano”, CCCXXXIX, 1981, 1, pp. 97–138; Idem, L’ultima spedizione garibaldina in Grecia (1912), in: Indipendenza e unità nazionale in Italia e in Grecia (Atti del convegno di studi tenuto in Atene nell’ottobre 1985), Firenze, Olschki 1987, pp. 191–220. L’ÉVOLUTION DE LA CLASSE POLITIQUE ROUMAINE AU XXe SIÈCLE GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA Pour parler de la classe politique roumaine, aujourd’hui, on a besoin avant tout de comprendre ce que la classe politique signifie, puis, on doit observer ce qui s’est passé dans ce pays dans les années ’90 et par conséquent la manière dont les institutions roumaines fonctionnent. En ce qui concerne le premier problème, ce que la classe politique représente, on doit entreprendre quelque chose de plus en rapport avec ce qu’on a appris des classiques italiens Mosca, Pareto, Michels, pour clarifier le sens et la signification du concept ayant comme point de départ la bibliographie assez riche concernant la thématique existante dans la pensée politique contemporaine. Par conséquent, dans l’opinion de Gaetano Mosca, la classe politique représente tout simplement une classe spéciale — un groupe de personnes qui accomplissent certaines fonctions politiques au sens strict. Un ensemble qui est constitué des personnes qui occupent des positions dominantes dans les différentes branches de la hiérarchie économique, intellectuelle et sociale. Elles sont les personnes qui contribuent à la distribution du pouvoir et, ce qui est très important, de la richesse. En même temps, ces groupes exercent le commandement politique «substantiel» au sens le plus simple de l’expression. Il s’agit donc de la classe dominante de point de vue économique, des riches, des groupes d’intellectuels, du clergé, des techniciens, des opérateurs économiques, des professionnels, des leaders de syndicats et en général de l’entière capacité dirigeante d’un pays, matérielle ou morale, civile ou religieuse, spontanée ou coercitive1. Mais pour comprendre le second problème il est nécessaire de faire un court historique concernant la classe politique roumaine et la situation de Roumanie et, en particulier, on doit parler de l’ainsi-dite «révolution roumaine». Pour cette raison, on peut dire que tous les problèmes d’aujourd’hui, avec leurs complications et leurs difficultés, ont comme point de départ la révolution roumaine. On pourrait dire, ainsi, que «la révolution roumaine» est vraiment comme «un péché originaire» à cause des conséquences politiques et du fonctionnement des institutions roumaines actuelles. Il est bien connu qu’aujourd’hui, particulièrement après la chute du mur de Berlin, on parle presque partout d’un processus «d’expansion» de la Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 54–64, Bucharest, 2005. 2 L’ÉVOLUTION DE LA CLASSE POLITIQUE ROUMAINE AU XXe SIÈCLE 55 démocratie au monde, une véritable offensive du système démocratique sur notre entière planète, un processus plus visible maintenant au début de notre siècle. L’institution des régimes politiques démocratiques dans les pays de l’Europe Centrale et de l’Est a été peut-être l’événement le plus résonant et discuté2 des années ’90. Un pas en avant, dans le cadre d’un tel processus ont connu, apparemment, les pays groupés sous la dénomination de «groupe de Visegrade, par comparaison aux autres pays de l’Europe de l’Est parmi lesquels la Roumanie représente un cas particulier. Mais, à la fin de l’année 1996, avec les élections parlementaires et présidentielles, on a réalisé en Roumanie l’alternance au pouvoir, un fait qui, en ce qui concerne les élections parlementaires, s’est passé pour la première fois après une période d’environ 70 ans, et avec la transformation de la Roumanie en État semi-présidentiel*; le phénomène est considéré unique. Ce relatif délai dans l’accomplissement du processus démocratique dans la Roumanie d’aujourd’hui a eu et a encore plusieurs causes objectives et subjectives, qui se dissimulent dans la profondeur des réalités sociales spécifiques roumaines (sédimentées pendant presque cinquante années de dictature de type stalinienne), avec des racines qui se perdent au début du XIXe siècle. On doit faire avant tout une précision: à partir de l’année 1938, en Roumanie on n’organise plus d’élections vraiment démocratiques, et la vie politique roumaine n’a plus possédé un réel caractère parlementaire. Un tel phénomène a été analysé et présenté d’une manière ample et brillante par Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu dans ces célèbres ouvrages: Sous trois dictatures et Problèmes fondamentaux de la Roumanie3. De tels aspects et états de choses, présentés ci-dessus, expliquent, croyonsnous, même partiellement, pour quoi l’on parle, aujourd’hui d’un retard du processus d’institution d’une démocratie parlementaire en Roumanie. On peut poser, d’une manière naturelle, une autre question: y a-t-il vraiment une démocratie dans la Roumanie contemporaine? La réponse est, certainement, affirmative. Mais pour comprendre les vicissitudes d’une naissance si difficile (de la démocratie dans la Roumanie postcommuniste), il s’impose la nécessité d’une courte incursion historique. Et pour anticiper et comprendre mieux tout ce qui s’est passé en Roumanie sous l’aspect de la démocratie parlementaire, les mots d’Antonio Gramsci — «l’ancien meurt, et le nouveau n’est pas encore né» — expriment, peut-être de la plus suggestive manière, comment se sont passées les choses dans cette période-là. Donc, est-ce que la Roumanie a eu une démocratie parlementaire pendant les décennies de l’entre-deux-guerres? On peut donner à une première analyse une réponse affirmative. Mais, à une investigation plus profonde, on va arriver immédiatement aux conclusions devenues communes d’un personnage de Caragiale, notre démocratie «est admirable, sublime même, mais elle manque totalement». À * Le professeur Sartori, un observateur attentif et avisé de la vie politique roumaine actuelle, n’est pas d’accord avec cette caractérisation (voir la revue “Studia Politica”, no. 1, 2002). 56 GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA 3 la même conclusion est arrivé un excellent analyste de la période de l’entre-deuxguerres, à savoir le sociologue français d’origine roumaine Matei Dogan. Il affirmait, dans un livre paru au cours de l’année 1946: «On ne peut pas soutenir qu’en Roumanie pendant la période de l’entre-deux-guerres il a existé un régime démocratique authentique»4. En faisant référence au même contexte, cet analyste politique précisait d’une manière plus détaillée: «On doit... reconnaître que n’importe quelle démocratie présente un décalage entre la théorie et la réalité. Pourtant, on peut dire que nulle part ce décalage n’a été plus profond qu’en Roumanie, le pays qui n’a pas connu une démocratie réelle. La souveraineté populaire a existé seulement du nom et le droit électoral n’avait rien d’un régime représentatif... On a lutté trop peu pour les libertés pour les comprendre. Le peuple est resté calme tandis qu’à la surface on a fait une délicate révolution. L’éducation politique manquait (elle manque même aujourd’hui — n.s. G.L.S.). Il y avait plusieurs principes, mais on ne réalisait aucun progrès5. Comment se présente en réalité le système démocratique parlementaire dans la Roumanie de l’entre-deux-guerres, ou plus précisément, en quoi consiste l’originalité de la démocratie appliquée dans cette période, nous explique toujours le professeur Dogan dans son ouvrage L’analyse statistique de la démocratie parlementaire de Roumanie. Il parle de la période antérieure à l’institution des dictatures, de la période d’avant 1938. Ainsi, dans le parlement roumain — nous dit-il — il n’a pas existé une majorité et une minorité, mais une majorité gouvernementale dominante qui anéantissait l’opposition. Une telle majorité gouvernementale était constituée des membres appartenant à un des deux partis de gouvernement qui occupaient alternativement le pouvoir et procédaient à l’organisation des élections parlementaires. Dans le parlement roumain la majorité gouvernementale n’a pas collaboré avec l’opposition, même si les deux partis au gouvernement n’ont pas eu de programmes tellement différents et leur collaboration aurait été possible. En outre, cette majorité gouvernementale du parlement ne représentait pas la majorité du corps électoral. Une minorité du corps électoral représentée au parlement par une dominante majorité, disposait, par l’intermédiaire de l’exercice du gouvernement, d’un pouvoir dictatorial. La majorité gouvernementale alternait au parlement avec une autre majorité gouvernementale qui n’entendait pas de collaborer avec l’opposition. Le régime n’était pas dictatorial, mais autoritaire: il procédait à la consultation du corps électoral, une consultation pourtant forcée et formelle dans le contexte où le corps électoral n’était pas caractérisé par la maturation politique. C’était un régime parlementaire démagogique. Ce régime était d’ailleurs fortement critiqué, dans cette période, par toutes les forces politiques et par les grands esprits du temps. Mis en doute, contesté directement par les légionnaires, le régime parlementaire a reçu le coup final de leur part. Pour comprendre mieux l’originalité d’un tel système on doit souligner que, pendant cette période, même s’il existait une Constitution démocratique, une 4 L’ÉVOLUTION DE LA CLASSE POLITIQUE ROUMAINE AU XXe SIÈCLE 57 généralisation du suffrage universel, en Roumanie l’organisation des élections a été réalisée d’une manière difficile. D’abord on désignait le Premier ministre, membre d’un des deux partis dominants, puis celui-ci organisait les élections et il les gagnait. C’était le roi qui, en réalité, detenait la «clé» du pouvoir réel en Roumanie de l’entre-deux-guerres. Cet état de choses a été exprimé d’une manière symbolique a été paraphrasé par un politicien comme Petre Carp qui avait prononcé, au parlement, les mots suivants: «Donnez-moi le pouvoir et je vous donnerai le parlement»6. «C’est banal de constater, mais c’est triste en même temps, affirmait S.S. Danielopol, que les changements du gouvernement n’ont été jamais faits avec l’accord du parlement, qu’a peu près tous les gouvernements qui abandonnaient le pouvoir disposaient, dans l’assemblée représentante du pays, d’une majorité accablante... il n’est pas exagéré de dire qu’en Roumanie il n’existe pas un pouvoir des lois...»7 la séparation des pouvoirs était seulement inscrite dans la Constitution, mais elle n’existait pas en réalité; en réalité un seul pouvoir existait: le pouvoir du gouvernement. Les principaux pouvoirs politiques dans la Roumanie de l’entre-deux-guerres qui concourraient à une telle rotation gouvernementale étaient le Parti National Paysan et le Parti National Libéral. C’est très intéressant de rappeler, dans ce contexte, que ces partis — nommés aussi «historiques» — reviendront au premier plan de la scène politique après les événements de 1989. De la sorte, la démocratie roumaine de cette époque, avec ces ingérences fréquentes de la Couronne dans la vie politique, avec l’inversement des rapports entre le gouvernement et le parlement dans le fonctionnement du régime représentatif et l’institution d’une prime électorale majoritaire excessive pour le parti qui obtenait de cette manière 40% des suffrages, a été beaucoup surestimée. Dans la Roumanie des années ’90, il semblait que les partis «historiques» aient voulu «restaurer» la situation qui caractérisait la période de l’entre-deuxguerres. Ce fait ne s’était passé nulle part dans les autres pays de l’Europe Centrale et de l’Est. La forme de démocratie politique roumaine de l’entre-deuxguerres y compris celle parlementaire, a été considérée comme une démocratie incomplète, «mimétique». La plupart de la population n’a pas perçu ce régime parlementaire comme un réel régime démocratique. Les élites roumaines affirmaient souvent leurs intérêts de classe, d’ordre économique et social, intérêts asymétriques par rapport à la réalisation d’un régime effectivement démocratique8. Se passe-t-il, aujourd’hui, la même chose dans la société roumaine? Est-ce que l’histoire se répète dans l’espace carpatodanubiano-pontique? Il s’agit de quelques questions auxquelles on s’est proposé de répondre, dans cette analyse, même si de manière partielle. Comme l’on a rappelé auparavant, la démocratie de l’entre-deux-guerres a été perçue de manière incorrecte par la population. Cet aspect a été «exploité» intensément après 1944, lorsqu’on a beaucoup usé des formules de propagande telles que: la «large concentration démocratique», 58 GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA 5 «le bloc national démocrate», etc., mais on ignorait souvent les libertés et les droits de l’homme les plus élémentaires. On est arrivé, on sait, à la destitution des partis et des institutions démocratiques, à la destitution effective du régime parlementaire en Roumanie. Il s’agit des années où le régime de type communiste stalinien a été instauré, régime qui ne peut pas être qualifié de démocratique. La vie politique a commencé son développement autour du parti unique (du parti-Ètat), parti qui était dirigé par un groupe restreint de personnes qui étaient à leur tour soumises au leader unique, etc. Il faut quand-même souligner le fait que le régime s’est basé sur un consensus social assez fort, sur l’existence de quelques droits sociaux véritables et sur l’accès large des à l’instruction. De tels «droits» sociaux ont assuré au régime de type stalinien (tel est le cas dans tous les pays où le regime communiste s’est développé) une certaine stabilité et une autonomie relative, fortement conditionnées cependant par le contexte des relations internationales. Beaucoup d’analystes et d’interprètes du phénomène politique roumain perdent totalement de vue de tels faits et ignorent l’existence de ce «consensus social» à l’intérieur de l’ancien régime communiste. Mais pendant les événements de la fin de l’année 1989 et du début de l’année 1990, il y a eu au moins deux tendances en Roumanie9, très différentes, concernant l’institution d’une nouvelle société; il y a eu même une troisième tendance, qui s’est pourtant manifestée d’une manière tacite. La première tendance a été celle «restauratrice» qui visait — tel qu’on a essayé de le mentionner plus haut — le retour à la pratique et à la conception de l’entre-deux-guerres, et qui ignorait en même temps presque tout ce qu’il y a eu de positif (surtout dans le plan culturel et social dans les années du «socialisme»). Il s’agit de la tendance représentée par les «partis historiques» (P.N.Þ–C.D. et P.N.L., et dans une certaine mesure le P.S.D. aussi). Cette tendance a été pourtant sérieusement amendée aux urnes (les premières élections démocratiques sous le contrôle international), à cause de leur faible prestation politique. Il faut rappeler ici un slogan célèbre utilisé par les représentants d’un certain «parti historique»: «chassez les loups» (allusion à la derise d’un parti rival). Une autre explication, beaucoup plus nuancée, serait celle que, avant les élections de 1990, P.N.Þ. et P.N.L. n’ont pas fonctionné dans l’espace public en tant que partis politiques, mais seulement en tant que symboles faciles à reconnaître, représentants d’une bipolarité idéologique qui mimait la fonction politique. Ce qui explique, en bonne partie, leur échec devant un électorat qui n’avait pas de motifs pour comprendre l’enjeu de la dispute idéologique10. Une deuxième tendance, qui a eu finalement la primauté et a dominé longtemps la scène de la vie politique roumaine, a été celle représentée par «les élites» qui se sont formées et préparées durant le régime communiste. Ces «élites» connaissaient mieux les réalités du pays, par leur qualité d’anciens directeurs d’entreprises, «élites» de l’ancien régime communiste, contestateurs de Ceauºescu, parfois même dissidents, et impressionnaient le public par leur grande réceptivité au nouveau. 6 L’ÉVOLUTION DE LA CLASSE POLITIQUE ROUMAINE AU XXe SIÈCLE 59 Il s’agit du groupement de forces politiques qui s’est revendiqué de l’acte du 22 décembre et qui a compris alors le mieux la réalité du pays, qui s’est mieux adapté à la situation nouvelle et a gagné de point de vue électoral. Cette tendance s’est groupée autour du F.S.N., une sorte de front populaire (qui est resté comme tel même après sa rupture en plusieurs factions et sa transformation en parti) qui trouvait son liant dans la personnalité de Ion Iliescu. F.S.N., et plus tard P.D.S.R., s’est proposé l’institution du régime parlementaire démocratique, cette revendication étant un des premiers points énoncés dans la Déclaration–Programme du C.F.S.N., dans la nuit du 22 décembre 1989. Il y avait des tensions aiguës entre les deux tendances et on réalisait très difficilement des ententes politiques pour pouvoir bâtir le régime parlementaire roumain. On trouve ici les causes de beaucoup d’erreurs passées durant ces années, de retards et même d’involutions. «Les partis historiques» ont refusé la participation au gouvernement en 1992, fait qui a rendu encore plus difficile le processus de modernisation et restructuration, avec des implications qui touchaient même à notre processus d’intégration européenne, sur la question de la mise en place de la réforme en général. D’autre part, le P.D.S.R. a s’est parfois caractérisé par des actions étranges, pleines d’arrogance, se contentant de son statut de «parti» de la majorité relative, en collaborant seulement avec des partis mineurs de point de vue de la représentation parlementaire et jouissant d’un prestige très bas au niveau de toute la population. Il y a eu, tel qu’on l’a dit plus haut, une troisième tendance, moins représentée au plan politique et parlementaire, mais beaucoup plus diffuse et plus répandue dans l’ensemble de la société roumaine. Cette tendance est manifeste chez les «véritables» nostalgiques du régime à peine disparu. J’ai mis ici en relief, de manière succincte, l’existence des forces politiques, car la réalisation d’un consensus politique en Roumanie a dépendu en grande partie de celles-ci, aspect qui a été conditionné à son tour par le processus d’institution du cadre démocratique parlementaire dans notre pays. Il est bien évident qu’en l’absence des partis politiques, il n’y a pas de démocratie. Or, dans le cas de notre pays, même si à un moment donné il y avait plus de 200 partis, peux d’entre eux étaient dignes d’un tel titre, et parfois ceux ayant une majorité relative au parlement avaient encore besoin d’un long chemin jusqu’à ce qu’ils deviennent des partis dans le vrai sens du mot. En tout cas, à partir des premières années après 1989 et jusqu’à présent, il y a eu en Roumanie un pluripartisme ample. Mais l’expérience roumaine plus récente (son caractère d’exception, d’une certaine manière) est significative aussi d’un autre point de vue, qui est cependant trop peu mentionné aujourd’hui. On doit tenir compte du fait qu’en Roumanie la domination écrasante du totalitarisme de Ceauºescu a déterminé son écroulement par une «destruction» de l’État (ancien, socialiste), y compris des nombreux liants de l’administration publique et de quelques institutions essentielles. «Le vide» de pouvoir qui a été créé ainsi 60 GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA 7 a été accompagné ensuite par une crise d’autorité prolongée du nouveau pouvoir, des nouvelles institutions qui se voulaient démocratiques, de l’État de droit, dont l’articulation a commencé avec les élections de 1990. Les effets de cette grave crise d’autorité de l’État sont encore aujourd’hui ressentis. La crise d’autorité de l’État a fait qu’en Roumanie, peut-être plus que dans les pays voisins, l’évolution vers la mise en place et la formation d’un régime démocratique soit marquée par des phénomènes amples d’anarchie sociale — on souligne ici les phénomènes et non pas les simples actes —, par des actions antisociales amples en plan économique et civique, qui ont affecté encore plus et de manière négative la fortune nationale, en traumatisant la société civile. On a tout simplement méconsidéré beaucoup de lois antérieures, qui continuaient par leur objet à être nécessaires, parfois même sans les normes élémentaires de la vie sociale dans l’ensemble, sans mentionner quelques décisions du nouveau pouvoir d’État. Cependant, la constitution graduelle d’un État démocratique (un parlement bicaméral), l’élaboration et l’approbation de la Constitution par le référendum de décembre 1991 sont seulement les prémisses obligatoires de la formation d’une société démocratique, sans que les deux processus s’identifient. Entre les deux il y a cependant un manque de synchronie réelle, une asymétrie, car le développement d’une société démocratique représente un objectif beaucoup plus complexe que le simple bâtiment des institutions de l’État de droit. La réalisation d’une société démocratique est liée à la stabilité et au progrès dans le domaine économique de la société, sans lequel réaliser l’intégration sociale authentique ne peut pas devenir possible. Une société démocratique est conditionnée aussi par la création et l’existence d’une vaste tradition démocratique et de la société civile, des groupes sociaux qui la composent, d’une conduite sociale meilleure et des mœurs sociales. Une société démocratique implique, en même temps, non seulement le bon fonctionnement des institutions parlementaires, le respect des droits de l’homme et des libertés du citoyen, mais aussi l’implémentation active des valeurs et des normes de la démocratie dans les mentalités collectives et individuelles. Dans la Roumanie d’aujourd’hui, on peut donc dire que l’on a jeté les bases institutionnelles d’un fonctionnement adéquat d’un régime démocratique parlementaire. On respecte, autrement dit, les normes et les règles qui rendent possible le jeu démocratique, de la manière dont l’a précisé récemment dans l’ouvrage Règles et valeurs de la démocratie le professeur Umberto Cerroni: la règle du consensus, de la compétition, de la majorité, de la minorité et de l’alternance, du contrôle, de la légalité11. Il n’y manque qu’une, qui est d’ailleurs la plus importante: la règle de la responsabilité. Cette situation fait que chez nous la démocratie paraisse être une façade et, ce qui est beaucoup plus grave encore, qu’en Roumanie le consensus social ait manqué et manque encore. C’est un aspect qui met souvent en danger le 8 L’ÉVOLUTION DE LA CLASSE POLITIQUE ROUMAINE AU XXe SIÈCLE 61 fonctionnement de la démocratie parlementaire roumaine. En même temps, la classe politique roumaine est soumise au changement. Mise à l’intersection entre le monde extérieur — la civilisation européenne et la globalisation l’affectent dans une mesure plus grande que n’importe quel autre composant de la société — et celui intérieur d’où elle provient et dont les caractéristiques elle tend à reproduire, la classe politique roumaine a été, probablement, la plus agitée et la plus dynamique partie de la période de transition12. Dans son évolution deux choses ont été importantes: d’un côté, le besoin de répondre aux besoins du contexte, parfois convergents et plus souvent contradictoires. Ce besoin a été une leçon que les nouveaux politiciens roumains ont apprise au moment où l’on a prouvé que n’importe quel élément du contexte pouvait décider, d’une manière directe ou indirecte, le destin des groupes ou des partis politiques. L’électorat roumain a réussi à le faire par les élections qui ont eu lieu. Le fait que certains partis ou groupes de politiciens ont disparu de la scène politique a obligé les hommes politiques à tenir compte de la population. La reconstruction de la classe politique roumaine a été faite, dans l’opinion d’un chercheur avisé de la vie politique roumaine (à savoir Sorina Soare), ayant comme point de départ la reconstruction et l’évolution des partis politiques roumains après 1990. De la sorte, si l’on observe la typologie des partis politiques roumains apparus après les événements des années ’89–’90, ceux-ci ont peuvent être considérés comme: — des partis héréditaires (formations politiques qui ont eu des liaisons avec le P.C.R.): F.S.N., P.D.S.R., P.R.M. et d’autres; — des partis de l’ainsi-dite «page blanche» (qui n’ont eu aucune liaison avec le passé): A.P.R; — des partis ou le groupe des dissidents: P.A.C.; — des partis historiques (P.N.Þ.–C.D., P.N.L., P.S.D.). En fonction de leurs intérêts spécifiques ou de combinaisons originales, on a vu se configurer la classe politique en Roumanie. Donc, c’est ainsi que s’explique pourquoi la scène politique postdécembriste est caractérisée par cette agglomération de partis qui ont affiché parfois de graves confusions terminologiques au niveau de la doctrine et du langage des leaders. Toutes ces choses expliquent le comportement des leaders et de la classe politique dans la Roumanie postcommuniste. Mais, en étroite liaison avec un tel comportement des leaders et de la classe politique roumaine, il faut mettre en évidence le caractère des institutions de Roumanie. Sur ces territoires, entre le Danube et les Carpates, depuis 150 années on parle de modernisation. D’une façon ou d’une autre, la modernisation signifiait une adaptation des formes d’organisation institutionnelle aux formes de l’Occident européen, la création ou la fondation de certaines institutions et un règlement constitutionnel. C’était un genre de transition vers l’Europe et depuis un siècle et demi chez nous on a eu... une permanente transition. On a parlé beaucoup dans la culture roumaine «des formes sans fond», «du retard historique» 62 GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA 9 des institutions roumaines, de ces formes nouvelles «inadaptées au fond roumain» et même des conditions «du dépassement du retard». Dans cette période-là, l’adaptation aux institutions européennes équivalait à un processus de synchronisation. La Roumanie désirait , et a toujours désiré, être contemporaine avec l’Europe. Enfin, n’a-t-on pas chez nous on en a beaucoup parlé — fait qui est bien connu — et des ouvrages célèbres illustrent cette réalité. Tous connaissent Caragiale et les répliques de certains de ses personnages d’Une lettre perdue. Le grand dramaturge ironisait l’existence d’une obsession. Mais une transition et une modernisation des institutions politiques ont eu pourtant lieu dans une première période, jusqu’aux années ’30. Durant la période de l’entre-deux-guerres il a existé chez nous une modernisation et une certaine stabilité institutionnelle. L’interrogation qu’on peut formuler sur cet aspect serait la suivante: pourquoi on n’a pas maintenu une telle stabilité? En ce qui concerne ceci, il s’imposerait le besoin d’une clarification. Nous tentons aussi de présenter un point de vue. Mais d’abord on doit souligner que la réponse pourrait être donnée même après une première analyse et elle est souvent répétée: les étrangers sont les coupables, les Turcs, les Russes (les bolcheviks) et d’autres. Et si au XVIIIe siècle, les traditionalistes, les conservateurs et d’autres transformaient notre retard historique dans un argument de l’indigénité, pendant le siècle suivant tous les faits historiques négatifs étaient liés à l’étranger. Et peut-être les choses se sont-elles expliquées de la sorte, au moins partiellement. Mais ce n’étaient pas les communistes et ni une force étrangère qui’ont annulé les Constitutions de 1923 en 1938. C’est vrai, ils l’ont fait dix ans plus tard. Mais le processus d’instabilité constitutionnelle a des origines plus anciennes. Ainsi, nous-pouvons passer à l’analyse proprement dite de notre intervention. Une «traduction» plus moderne des mots du grand Florentin peut être exprimée de la manière suivante: «Personne n’est au-dessus la loi». Et à cause du fait que personne n’est au-dessus la loi on doit avoir un bon fonctionnement des institutions. C’est d’ailleurs l’essence de la politique: «L’objet de recherche de la politique n’est pas l’homme mais les institutions», soutient John Plamenatz, les institutions, il est bien connu, supposent des normes et des lois. Pour cette raison, on a besoin des lois fondamentales. Au début, chez nous il y avait les règlements (organiques), tout comme chez les Italiens (toujours au début) c’était le statut qui réglementait la vie politique, et je fais référence à la période du Risorgimento. Mais jusqu’à présent notre pays a connu environ dix Constitutions, règlements ou lois fondamentales, quel que soit leur nom. On croit que l’instabilité constitutionnelle trouve son origine ici. Chaque régime qui s’instaurait imposait sa propre Constitution. L’ancien régime, celui d’avant 1990, a eu trois Constitutions et par comparaison il est nécessaire de mentionner que les États-Unis ont eu une seule Constitution dans une période de plus de 200 ans (1787). Les institutions accomplissent une fonction socialisante dans la mesure où elles orientent et réglementent les comportements des individus et la société 10 L’ÉVOLUTION DE LA CLASSE POLITIQUE ROUMAINE AU XXe SIÈCLE 63 qu’ils composent. Elles développent un rôle préceptorial (dans le sens d’imposition d’un précepte, d’une norme, d’une règle), selon le politologue américain Ch. Lindblom (en 1997). De cette manière, les bons citoyens font les bonnes institutions, et les bonnes institutions sont bonnes dans la mesure où elles produisent et forment de bons citoyens, et ceux-ci les trouvent appropriées, ne les perçoivent pas comme «étrangères», ne sont pas aliénés par rapport à elles. Les «bonnes» institutions développent un sens de la loyauté et contribuent à l’adoption et à la consolidation de ces «attentes cognitives ou institutions morales» dont elles-mêmes (en tant qu’institutions) tirent leur origine. La fonction «préceptoriale» ou hégémonique que les institutions (qui opèrent avec succès) développent a, grosso modo, un caractère négatif (Claus Offe): elles encouragent chez les acteurs sociaux une auto-imposition de la discipline du comportement qui fait que soient tenues sous contrôle les actions opportunistes. Une telle appréciation peut trouver des références également dans la Roumanie d’aujourd’hui. D’autre part, les institutions fournissent aux acteurs sociaux des standards sociaux validés concernant les préférences et les objectifs autorisés et qui attendent leur autorisation (approbation). La présence ou l’absence des deux liaisons opératives de feed-back — discipline et autorisation — représentent le premier examen par l’intermédiaire duquel on peut voir si un cadre social ou politique extérieur ou autre est une institution. Je lance, dans ce sens, une invitation à réfléchir sur les «institutions» de chez nous. La qualité des institutions peut être bien reprise de la perspective d’un autre examen: les institutions ne doivent pas suivre seulement des tâches que l’on pourrait nommer «socialisation congruente», elles deveaient fonctionner et celà d’une manière convenable, c’est-à-dire suivre des tâches ou missions établies par elles-mêmes ou être compétentes à fournir des ressources dont elles dépendent. Une institution qui fonctionne décharge ses acteurs des considérations finalistes ou bien stratégiques, dans la mesure où on fait confiance au fait qu’un cours institutionnel de l’action prescrite peut mener à des résultats bénéfiques ou moins tolérables. Une fois avoir atteints ces paramètres, les institutions fonctionnent en tant que pilote automatique. Mon idée de base est que toutes ces aspirations peuvent devenir réalité seulement (ou bien surtout) en partant de la réalisation d’une bonne Constitution, en harmonie avec les exigences européennes. «Les types idéaux» d’institutions que l’on a présentés plus haut sont-ils en parfaite consonnance avec les valeurs européennes, peuvent-ils être implantés sur le terrain roumain aussi? Je dirais, pour conclure, que le système constitutionnel de Roumanie n’est pas encore très bien fondé. Sa fonctionnalité est mise en danger par les nombreux changements institutionnels qui ne favorisent pas du tout la stabilité politique de notre pays. L’instabilité du législatif est encore présente. Le Conseil Supérieur de la Magistrature (C.S.M.), à peine constitué, va être l’une des institutions les plus discutées. Une telle instabilité politique et institutionnelle favorise et 64 GHEORGHE LENCAN STOICA 11 n’empêche point l’existence de la corruption. Les investisseurs étrangers qui sont intéressés au milieu d’affaires en Roumanie réclament, très soucieux, justement un tel chaos législatif. Dans la situation donnée, la faiblesse évidente de la classe politique de Roumanie influence beaucoup un tel chaos législatif et institutionnel. Même dans ces jours (juillet 2005) il y a un fort conflit entre la Cour Constitutionnelle et le gouvernement, entre le Parlement et le Président. Le seul facteur orientatif peut venir (comment il se passe toujours en Roumanie) de l’étranger. Aujourd’hui une telle fonction est accomplie par les Commissaires Européens. NOTES 1. Giorgio Sola, La teoria delle élites, Bologna, II Mulino, 2000, p.68. 2. Ralph Dahrendorph, Revoluþiile în Estul ºi Centrul Europei, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 1993, p.137. 3. Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu, Problemele de bazã ale României, 1946, p. l19. 4. Antonio Gramsci, Quaderni del carcere, Torino, Editura Einaudi, 1975, p. 1130. 5. Matei Dogan, Analiza statisticã a democraþiei parlamentare din România, Bucureºti, 1946, p. 109. 6. 7. 8. 9. Ibidem, p. l 10. Ibidem, p. 108. Ibidem, p. 106. Damian Hurezeanu, Democraþia azi, Bucureºti, Editura Noua Alternativã, 1995, p. 135. 10. Ibidem, p. 136. 11. Daniel Barbu, ªapte teme de politicã româneascã, Bucureºti, Editura Antet, 1997, p. 98. 12. Ibidem, p. 99. THE CULT OF PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM RODICA IAMANDI The Cult of Personality: Theoretical Foundations and Forms of Manifestation From the very beginning a warning is necessary, about the difficulty of the attempt to define the phrase “the cult of personality”. First of all, because in the present, the common sense, “adulation of a personality”, substituted itself to the much more complex meaning that this highly ideologically loaded expression had over the time. This is probably the reason why in the Romanian specific literature from after 1989, the cult of personality is defined as a political practice attributing an exaggerated role to a political personality within the evolution of society, producing a deformation of the whole political life of the country1 or as a systematic attitude provoked and controlled concerning a leader (or a personality) considered gifted with special qualities as intellectual, as sensitivity, as manager, as visionary etc., such as were considered to be Hitler, Stalin, Mao Zedong, Ceauºescu, Bokassa, Idi Amin2. An inventory of the definitions before 1990 (even if they were conceived from the perspective of Leninist-Marxist philosophy) brings along a plus of nuances on the topic. The theoreticians of the communist period noticed something that I have encountered myself, precisely that the name does not capture the whole complex of economical, social, political, ethical, ideological, etc. matters it refers to3. Second, in the literature in all the cases of exploitation and oppression of masses corresponding to the concentration of power in the hands of one a cult of personality is identified (as with the Pharaon in the ancient Egypt, the emperor in China, the absolute monarch in feudal Europe, the “Führer” in nazi Germany). Plus, in these works there is a theoretical foundation of the cult of personality within the cult of the “genius”, or of the “hero”, or of the “critical personality” as in the works of the romantics F. Schelling and Th. Carlyle, or in those of young hegeliens such as B. Bauer and N. Stirner, in the case of the Russian peasant 19th century revolutionaries, the Narodnics, or in the works of F. Nietzsche4. Finally, in the literature the idea that the cult of personality generates in the life of society a chain of phenomena contrary to the general human moral norms is underlined, since the ware attitude of the people towards accomplishing their social duty is replaced by the bind compliance to the will of the deified leader, to whomever Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 65–80, Bucharest, 2005. 66 RODICA IAMANDI 2 bears the supreme authority, contributing to the spread of amoral methods of defense for the existing order5. The essential contribution to bringing the meaning of “the cult of personality” into shape had Nikita Sergheevici Khrushchev, when at the 20th of the Communist Party of the Soviet Union (CPSU, from now on) 1956 Congress, has condemned the cult of comrade Joseph Vissarionovich Dzhugashvili, called Stalin. In the official report, presented at the Congress, Khrushchev says: “the C.C. has taken a determined attitude against the cult of personality, foreign to the spirit of Marxism-Leninism, cult that transforms this or that activist into a hero working wonders, at the same time minimizing the role of the party and of popular masses, leading to diminishing their creative activity. The spread of the cult of personality has decreased the role of collective rule within the party and often it has brought about serious deficiencies in our work”6, and the C.C. shall analyze in June 1956 the objective conditions that were in favor of the spreading of the cult of personality, along with the subjective factors, resulted from the personal qualities of Stalin, in a decision entitled “On doing away with the cult of personality and with its consequences”. Apparently, in the “Secret discourse”7, to which foreign delegates had no access to, Khrushchev was much harsher, denouncing Stalin’s crimes. It is due to this specific association between the cult of personality and the name of Stalin that many political analists consider “the cult of personality” a “ideological euphemism for the entire system of lies, corruption, mass crimes and universal fear”8. To understand better how stalinism was built, the analysis of Raymond Aron is extremely useful. The author identifies five phases in the history of the Russian Bolshevik Party. “During the forth phase, that of the absolute power of Stalin, all major decisions are taken by a single man. This man is surrounded by his comrads with whom he discusses within the Politburreau, but to whom he is incapable to impose his will and whom, starting 1934, begins even to terrorize, the factions are eliminated with no mercy, not only politically, but also physically. The oponents, either real or vitual, within the party, are considered traitors; they are killed either after they were solemnly trialed and this sentence was pronounced following their ‘confession’, or they are eliminated in prison.”9 Within such a system, it is obvious that the power is situated at the top of the party hierarchy and that a single man has it. “A person and that person alone was deciding the fate of all others, covering them in glory or shame, transforming the servants of the régime into fiddles or into traitors.”10 After Khrushchev, the beginning of Stalin’s cult of personality is marked by the terrorism of the years 1934–1938, oriented against party members, at first to end the life of Stalin’s already defeated adversaries, then to strike the most devoted of the Stalinists. “Why was terrorism directed against the very militants of the communist party who did not deviate from the line of the party? To this question, Khrushchev offers only one answer, one single interpretation: the cult of personality. Or, all one can say is that this is actually no answer, no explanation.”11 It seems that Stalin was at the origin of the notion “enemy of the people” and that this expression made possible the use of the most terrible 3 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 67 oppression, against anyone who would in any manner whatsoever disagree with Stalin. “When Stalin said that this person or the other had to be arrested, it had to be admitted on word basis that it is about an enemy of the people, and then Beria’s clique, in charge of the state Security organs, would go above themselves to prove the guilt of the person arrested and to sustain the documents they forged. What kind of proofs they provided? The convicts’ (were provided) confessions, and the judges were taking these seriously. And how can be confessed crimes never committed? In only one way, after applying physical forms of constraint, tortures generating lack of conscience, intellectual confusion, of deprivation of human dignity”12 — as it was said in a fragment of Khrushchev’s text. According to Raymond Aron’s opinion, The Secret Report of Khrushchev’s offers a singular illustration for the theory of Montesquieu on despotism, the theory according to which the principle of despotism is fear — an insidious fear — progressively taking over all individuals inside a collectivity. To the question “Why didn’t we do anything?” Khrushchev answers “with sincerity and naïvety”: “it was impossible for us to undertake any action. Whenever we were convoqued by the supreme leader, we never knew if it was in order to consulte us concerning an important decision, or to throw us away in Lubianka prison”13. Whichever the theory of history adopted at some point, we have to take the individuals into consideration a well. In order to go from potential to real, from the intelligible functions of epuration to the lack of measure within the real, ample process of epuration, it was needed an unique ingredient, a man, Stalin himself. One should not minimize the role this person/personality has played due to that absolute power that he has possessed. At the same time, the phenomena called “the cult of personality” are not indebted only to the particularities of an unique man, but also to the technique of organisation and action of a certain party, which explains the apparison of the cult of personality within the satellite communist countries and around the leaders of those states, as well. After some historians, the cult of Stalin appeared in the period 1926–1927. In many of the speache given by the “left-wing” oposition leaders, there was even then present the protest against Stalin’s cult of personality. Thus, at the 14th Congress of the Bolshevik Communist Party of the Soviet Union, by the end of December 1925, L. Kamenev has warned about the danger of amplification of the cult of some leaders and especially of Stalin’s: “We are against the creation of the theory of ‘the leader’, we are against the creation of ‘the leader’. We are against the Secretariate, in fact reuniting the politics and whole organisation, situating itself above the political organ… Personally I consider that our general secretary is not a personality to gather around a polarized old Bolshevik headquarters… Especially because I have told these personally and repeatedly to comrade Stalin, especially because I have told about these things repeatedly to the group of Leninist comrades, I repeat what I have said here at the Congress: I have reached the conclusion that comrade Stalin cannot fulfil the role of polarizing agent for the Bolshevik head-quarters.”14 This was though only the beginning of Stalin’s ascension. Apparently he manifested a heavy democratism, almost in contrast with the “aristocratic” Trotsky. 68 RODICA IAMANDI 4 Stalin was realtively accessible, rude and simple. He walked around free through the C.C. building and Kremlin, almost without any guard. Sometimes he stopped by unanounced at the Institute of Red Professors to talk to the students. If at the beginning of the third decade in most official institutions there could be seen portraits of Lenin and Trotsky (after 1924, Trotsky’s protrait was taken down everywhere), Stalin’s portrait would not appear anywhere; it started to be displayed everywhere only from 1930 on, after in 1929, with a pomp unnatural for the times, Stalin was celebrated at his 50 anniversary. In the messages received to congratulate him would not make presence only words as “wonderful”, “top”, but also words like “grand” and “genius”. The collection of articles and memories about Stalin, issued in 1929, contained many exagerations and deformations of the facts. The idea that “during Lenin, comrade Stalin, one of his disciples”, was at the same time his greatest help, who, different from others, in all the important phases of the revolution, in all the decisive moments of activity of the party led by Vladimir Ilich “went side by side with him, without any hesitation”15. Some of the authors of this collection attempted to prove that even though Stalin was more of a practician within the party, in reality he was an important theoretician of Marxism-Leninism. In an article entitled Stalin and the Red Army, K.E. Voroshilov attributes to Stalin not existent merits in the Civil War. Thus, in 1931, in the preface to the six volumes edition of Lenin’s works, the editor, V.V. Adoratski, to affirm that Lenin’s works have to be studied with a Stalin perspective in mind. E. Iaroslavski and A. Bubnov, the authors of the history books of the Bolshevik Communist Party of the Soviet Union, have included pages consecrated to Stalin’s merits. The eulogies, that have considerably increased in number after the C.C. plenary meeting of January 1933, were not, maybe, totally lacking sincerity; but they were essentially full of the zeal of flattery, carefully stimulated. The fact that the first to resort to limitless eulogy were the members of his Political Bureau, especially Molotov and Kaganovich, confered those eulogies imediately the character of an official political line to be followed as well by those who have never considered Stalin infailible. Stalin’s flattery chorus was added with voices of former oposition leaders, whose voices were at times even louder that those of the others. Zinoviev and Kamenev, for example, were publishing articles where they were admitting their mistakes and recognizing how right is “the great leader of workers worldwide — comrade Stalin”. In the first issue of 1934’s “Pravda” an article of H. Radek spoke of Stalin only in superlatives. After a couple of days the article became a brochure, edited in 225,000 copies. Stalin’s cult did not do it for his great vanity, but also for his thirst of power, situating his singularly, above the party and beyond any critique, fact obvious at the 17th Congress of the Bolshevik Communist Party of the Soviet Union, were each and every speaker was evoking the “greatness” and the “genius” of Stalin. Then, through Comintern, the cult of the Stalin was implemented within all communist parties from abroad. At the same time, the example of the Bolshevik 5 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 69 Communist Party of the Soviet Union stimulated the cult of the local leaders within the satellite communist countries. Forms of the Cult of Personality in Communist Romania before 1965 In Romania, the first signs of a cult of personality, in very shy forms in comparison to what it was yet to come, is noticed from the period when the communist party was not an unique political force within society, and they were dedicated especially to Ana Pauker. She came from Moscow along with the Red Army tanks, fact that gave her, in that specific pro-Soviet sate of mind of the time, a peculiar aureole; plus the intervention of the party propaganda that, overestimating her merits and revolutionary qualities, as it will next be the case with Dej, and, especially, with Ceauºescu — these factors made her a second Passionaria (after the name of Dolores Ibaruri). Along with her adulation a style was inaugurated, that will be continued also in the decades to come. “As she used to say herself, all happens because she expresses the highest knowledge, made accessible to all. Listening to them at the meetings, with the clear and determined voice, vibrating at her high wisdom, at her great love for people, each felt her close, as if she would speak only to them, about their lives, about their needs, and each listens to her all ears, absorbing every word and every thought.”16 Even in that time were manipulated notions like freedom, independence and sovereignty, as the idea of love for the country: “the ardent love for the country goes through as a red wire, all her activity, all her fight.”17 Thus, Ana Pauker arrives next to Gheorghiu-Dej and Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu, one of the main aspirants at the leadership of the party, dispute within which she counted on her links with the circles near Stalin, as on the support of certain key emigration comrades (Vasile Luca, Teohari Georgescu, Iosif Chiºinevski) with who she formed the so-called “external group”. Therefore, this acerb fight for supremacy within the party has dominated the history of Romania in the first decade after war, a fight conducted mainly between the exponents of the two groups — Gheorghiu-Dej, from the inside and Ana Pauker, from the outside, each trying to enter the grace of Stalin (the principal referee of this dispute). The minority ethnic origin of Ana Pauker (who has succeeded to win the trust and appreciation from Stalin and from the majority of persons in her entourage) has determined Moscow dictator to give the “winning cup”, eventually, to Gheorghiu-Dej, who had all the required qualities for a communist leader in that historical context, and, also, he was one devoted to Stalinism with all his being. Motivating his option Stalin addressed Molotov who sustained Ana Pauker: “Dear Viaceslav Mihailovici, Ana is a good comrade, trustworthy, but, the Romanian Party needs a leader from the working class, a true Romanian.”18 Hence, starting actually October 1945, at the National Conference, for almost two decades he will be — with short intermittence — the almighty character in Romania, both in what concerns the party and the state. Far from offering a solution to the fight for power once and for all, the dispute between the two teams continued, gaining often-tensioned accents. Dej’s 70 RODICA IAMANDI 6 anxiety was even bigger since the external group kept close links with Soviet institutions, especially with the N.K.V.D. of Beria; at the same time the group (Pauker, Luca, T. Georgescu) recognized the first secretary of the party at the plenary meeting from 1961 and they acted “as a group constituted singularly, outside the elected organs (…), most important matters of party leadership and of state being resolved by the secretariat and not by the Political Bureau (my note) where they had majority and where the secretary general, in many matters of great importance, was placed in a weaker position, left by himself”19. Given all these, Dej will be on the top of this situation, due to his less obvious qualities, untill that point — political ability, tact and diplomacy — waiting for favorable conditions for the final confrontation to appear, especially since he had Stalin’s accept, who, unsatisfied with the tensioned atmosphere within the party, said bluntly to Dej: “if they get in your way, scare them away!”20 The opportunity came along with the C.C. plenary meeting in 26–27 May 1952, met to discuss the serious deviations from party’s line of the former leadership of the Finance Ministry and of Popular Romania’s Bank, realizing that Vasile Luca “has separated himself from the party… has surrounded himself with party’s enemies, has stood up against the general line of the party”; that Teohari Georgescu “manifested conciliatory attitude related to the rightwing deviations of Vasile Luca”. Serious accusations Dej have for Ana Pauker, as well, saying that “the deviation from the party line in matters of agriculture and collections”, that “she has cultivated unprincipled relations within the party”. Considering all these, the plenary meeting reaches the conclusion that the exclusion of Vasile Luca21 from the C.C. and of Teohari Georgescu from the Political Bureau and from the C.C. secretariat are necessary, as later from the functions of vice-presidents of the Council of Ministers. Ana Pauker is sanctioned only with a warning, but the plenary does not elect her again as member in the secretariat and in the Political Bureau of the C.C., as a first step towards her final elimination from the leadership of the party22. The disparaging and removal of the “anti-party” group, of the “fraction” group Pauker-Luca-Georgescu from the leadership of the Romanian Worker’s Party and afterwards, entirely the elimination from the party has overcome, through the implications and consequences the sphere of a power struggle, given that with this decision internal political disputes were ended within the communist party that becomes hence a real “monolith party”, dominated in an authoritarian manner by a group with an unique political orientation and, in fact, by a single man who shall obtain thus the monopoly of personal power. Gheorghiu-Dej’s dictatorship over the party was exercised without mediation over the country as well and the cult of personality he generated was nothing else but a local Stalinism. Even if the cult of personality of Dej and his power inside the party got a considerable extension, he couldn’t yet consider himself entirely mastering the situation, as long as he felt his position within the party threatened by his eternal rival — Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu. The solution that he has chosen — at the advice and with the support of his obedient and zealous subordinate — Alexandru 7 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 71 Drãghici (minister of Internal Affairs) — was the harshest, that is the physical elimination of his adversary. As a consequence, Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu was arrested under the false accusation of “spionage in the service of imperialism” and “crime of high treason”. Then, he was tried, sentenced to death and executed in a great hurry, in the night of 16th to 17th of April 1954, “shot from behind”. Without any doubt, Gheorghiu-Dej and his minister of internal affairs, Drãghici, bear the main reponsability for this murder, but guilty and responsible was the entire leadership of the party at the time (the members of Political Bureau and of the C.C.). The latter could not exonerate themselves for initiating, encouraging and supporting the proliferation of the cult of personality of Dej, with unfortunate consequences for the entire Romanian society. They also have overlooked, encouraging a condemnable complicity, many abuses and illegalities to which the entire intellectual Romanian elite (many from the intellectually flourishing period between the two World Wars, but also other prominent figures in our science and culture) has fallen a victim to, given the inhumane regime of physical and moral extermination within that Romanian gulag. Even more, while in the Soviet Union stalinist crimes were uncovered and therefore society there was going through a profound process of conscience, in Romania there were very few signs of change, the Romanian Worker’s Party continuing to patronize a “society with rigid forms, leaded by perified dogmas, ‘stalinizing’ everything as an automat device that once started is impossible to be stopped, insulating all the possible niches through which the wind of thaw that, blowing throughout all Eastern Europe, could have blown inside Romania as well”23. The disappearance of Stalin, instead of giving Dej and his fiddels the opportunity of long awaited normalization of the domestic life, considered it an internal affair of the Soviet Union, ignoring the similar de-stalinisation process taking place within the most of the satellite countries from the center and southeastern Europe (the Hungarian revolution of 1956 being the most violent form of manifestation of this “political thaw”). Dej felt master of the situation both within the party and in the country, fact that permitted him to overcome succesfully the moment of Hungarian revolution, namely all the turmoil generated as consequence within Romanian young generation. Interior stability, plus the experience gained from the “Hungarian lesson” have decided Dej to take the next step, decisiv in what concerns foreign politics (that would bring him great popularity) — the parting with Moscow’s influence. The international context, dominated by the politics of relaxation generated by Khrushchev, was in his favor and his tactics of overstating the “RomanianSoviet friendship” and of the fidelity towards Moscow was as absurd as efficient. One has to notice that the ability and diplomacy have characterized the whole political career of the communist leader. This way Dej has obtained what no other satellite of Moscow has succeeded: the withdrawal of the quota of participation at “sovroms” and mainly the “miracle” of June1958, that is, the withdrawal of the Soviet troops that were stationed in Romania since 1944. These successes have consolidated internal stability bringing about a bonus of popularity to the communist leader, more than all party propaganda and more 72 RODICA IAMANDI 8 than the exacerbation of the cult of personality have accomplished. Starting the detachment from Soviet taking care of was a great merit of Dej, but unfortunately this did not mean for him de-stalinisation as well, as that started by Khrushchev at the 20th Congress of the Soviet Union Communist Party. For Gheorghiu-Dej — as Silviu Brucan recognized — soviet experience that he had piled up before, now has become an à la table menu, that is he was choosing from it just what suited him. It was a de-satellisation to save stalinism and not to reform it, as tried Khrushchev in the Soviet Union24. Dumitru Popescu says in a memoirs book that: “Our Stalin was not dead, our Stalin was defending himself”25, in relation to Dej’s attitude during 1958 campaign, when under a front of hits against those contaminated by the events in Hungary and Poland, was a hit against the critics of stalinism seen as a reaction to the cult of Stalin aimed at Dej, eventually. Even if only Miron Constantinescu and Iosif Chiºinevski were found scape-goats, according to Dumitru Popescu, “behind them were large categories of party activists eager to open a public political process of stalinism, including a process of the way Stalin reflected himself in our social reality and continued to reflect himself there because the generative factors were not removed”26. Under such circumstances, appears understandable the equivocous attitude of Dej towards the re-launching of the process of de-stalinisation in the Soviet Union at the 22nd Congress of the Soviet Union Communist Party, in October 1961. He could not afford neither to situate himself in a position of frond towards the orientation of the Congress and Khrushchev, nor to sustain openly the cult of Stalin. With charateristic ability he has found an “original” way to expose stalinism by taking it against his old oponents from the exterior group, during the plenary of C.C., from 30th of November – 5th of December 1961. The report presented by Dej at the plenary meeting considered fully justified “the measures taken by the Soviet Union Communist Party to end the cult of personality and its consequences”, under that influence “methods and practices contrary to leninist norms have taken place, oversteping the democratic rules in party life”, “but he added, the methods generated by the cult of personality and by its consequences did not have the extent they had in other countries”, because the party, his activists guarded “the fundamental principles of the party”, did not give way to presures* and unhesitatingly protected the life and the dignity of the party members27. The main attack was directed again towards “the anti-party group Pauker-Luca” and towards his supporters (Teohari Georgescu, Iosif Chiºinevski and Miron Constantinescu) — supposedly the main exponents of stalinist cult and practices, with old and new accusations, exposing for the first time their ill-fated role in cooperativisation of the agriculture, the fact that in spite of the indications of Ana Pauker to Teohari Georgescu “in the name of the struggle against kulaks, over eighty thousands of peasants, most of them working peasants were sent to trial”, under the accusation that they did not respected their obligations towards the state. * Neither internal, nor external — author’s note, R.I. 9 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 73 Transferring the responsibility for all inequalities and abuses to the “fraction groups”, Dej considered “a fortune for our party that their pressions did not result inequalitie, so there were no serious injustices done to be repared and no one was to be reabilitated post-mortem”28. In the same vein of falsifying the history, spoke many of the superior party leadership, among them excelling in demagogy and servility his successor at power, leader of the Romanian Communist Party (R.C.P.), Nicolae Ceauºescu. How sincere he was, showed seven years later, when he has launched a virulent critique aimed at the former leadership part of which he was too, as an opening act to the process he was going to intent to Dej. Ceauºescu was not concerned by the fate of the party or by the fate of Dej’s victims, but for personal reasons and mainly irritated by the fact that the parting with Moscow was initiated by Dej with good consequences seen already from 1964. “For a long while — declared Ceauºescu shortly after the plenary meeting from April 1968 — we used to think and to declare publicly with satisfaction that we have nothing to reabilitate, that in Romania abuses, violations of party democracy or of socialist legislation did not take place. Even more, it was said that it was a great happiness for us that we have had someone to protect the party and state activists.”29 Beyond the cynicism of the appreciations Dej made was the easy way he distanced himself from the responsibilities for many illegalities committed under his lead, saying: “we have nothing to rehabilitate”, ignoring knowingly the victims of the genocide of 1937–1938 including R.C.P. members, including the assassinates of ªtefan Foriº and Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu, ignoring knowingly the thousands of victims of the Romanian gulag after 1948. The reforming action triggered by Khrushchev at the 20th Congress of the Soviet Union Communist Party and developed at the 22nd, with all the positive effects for the new Soviet domestic politics encouraged same actions in the satellite countries from the eastern Europe, with first manifestations in Albania and Hungaria. Paradoxically, especially now when stalinism and the cult of personality were denounced, when profound changes were taking place, Dej and Romanian Worker’s Party were dominating the Romanian political scene. Dej was favored also by his united team of collaborators, consisting of specialists in varied fields and of devoted political men. Under his leadership there are accomplishments like the diplomatic solution to the Soviet-Chinese ideological conflict, from an appearently neutral standpoint, or the parting with Moscow*), or the general amnisty for political prisoners — surprising political decision even for the most ardent supporters of the régime. This amnisty was the unique liberating opportunity for many leading personalities of Romanian science and culture. All these events were the apogee of his career and brought about his large political support. An objective evaluation of Gheorghiu-Dej’s activity as leader of state, cannot omit the fact that in spite of the errors committed as consequence of his cult of personality, that has captured the masses due to his fermity in politics, he also led Romania to the general renewal path that has contained eastern Europe at the * With its climax marked by the Declaration from April (1964) — author’s note, R.I. 74 RODICA IAMANDI 10 beginning of 1964. As a benchmark for the new historical epoch for Romania, the Declaration from April (1964) was conceived by this party leader as a perspective program, but it became his political testament. There were stated two priorities: external political life stabilisation and internal stabilisation of the political life. He succeeded to accomplish only the first, obtaining with many risks the authonomy of the party, its inalienable right to manifest itself as a national political force, and especially, the relative independence of the country and its national sovereignity. “Even partially realized on this exterior dimension of it — notices Victor Frunzã — this work (left halfway) contributed to a different reception of Gheorghiu-Dej by the history, from, let’s say, the reception if he would have disappeared in 1956, not only with his hands tainted by the blood of thousands of victims, but with qualities that make him an important complex personality for our contemporary epoch… Most certainly Dej cannot be in trial for what he wanted to, but he did not succeed to accomplish. Posterity has to be grateful for what he has done good for the country and for the Romanian people.”30 Beyond these attainments there are errors that remain, though, very serious ones, like the crimes initiated and patronized for almost two decades, while he was gathering in his hands the entire power within the party and state. For this he was examined by a stern history and found guilty without any hesitation. The Cult of Personality practiced and imposed under Nicolae Ceauºescu The successes obtained by Gheorghiu-Dej, especially, on the level of the relative independence of the country and of the national sovereignity, were subordinated by his successor, Nicolae Ceauºescu, to his personal interest. The two deziderates became the leit-motif of an absurd propaganda campaign that would lead step by step towards setting up a dictatorship and a cult of personality without precedent in Romanian history. Ceauºescu’s road towards personal dictatorship was much more opressive than that of Dej, while it was set in place gradually by a chain of apparently inoffensive measures, but with dangerous implications for democracy. Although there were only three years since his confirmation at the 9th Congress of the party as secretary general of the C.C. of R.C.P., Nicolae Ceauºescu has accumulated already power. In December 1967 he has assumed for himself the function of president of the Council of State, so he was head of the state, too. He used it first to uncover the abuses and illegalities of the former leadership (except himself), aiming his attacks mainly at his rival Alexandru Drãghici and at Gheorghiu-Dej. The action was not ostentatious, all taking place in the second part of the C.C. of R.C.P. plenary meeting of April 1968, consecrated to the development of education at all levels and he did not himself even took the floor for this point in the order of discussions. He talked about this subject at another meeting (a meeting of the activists of Bucharest) in 26th of April. That plenary has represented, after Dumitru Popescu, “the climax of destalinization in Romania, its pick”31. Security was placed at its suited infamous place due to the role played on that stage of development of the socialist régime 11 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 75 (abuses, illegalities, crimes). Ceauºescu considered that those practices could not by blamed on the cult of personality as others did, but they are characteristic of “the states of economic, political, social and educational low level of the people and due the backward mentality of those who have committed all these crimes”, as phenomena outside socialism that should be left outside32. The plenary meeting has rehabilitated Lucreþiu Pãtrãºcanu, ªtefan Foriº and other victims of the cult of personality, as those condemned and executed in the Soviet Union at the order of Stalin during “Great Terror” years, 1937–1938. Also, eliminating the main culprit in Pãtrãºcanu’s case, Alexandru Drãghici, Ceauºescu gave a signal for the removal of all inconvenient people, all Dej close people, namely. His intransigent attitude in all matters of interest for the party and for the country, such as those tackled at the plenary from April 1968, or his firm position in the Czechoslovakia matter, condemning the Soviet intervention and that has propelled him in the posture of a national hero, as the population saw in him an ideal, more liberal leader, more democratic and more open to renewal than his predecessor. At the same time he became famous internationally, great leaders like Harold Wilson, de Gaulle, and Richard Nixon, rushing to visit him officially at Bucharest. The so-called liberation was only a relative one, though. Within the party he only did the traditional “rotation of the staff” to minimize or eliminate the influence of the “old guard”. Hence, in the party there was not possible to form a real opposition to the old Stalinist methods, to the ascension of a new cult of personality, but only singular voices were heard*. An eyewitness of the time considers that Czechoslovakia’s invasion was the decisive moment for the creation of a cult of personality for Ceauºescu: “in those moments a certain attitude imposed itself towards Ceauºescu within the party. As the word went back then, the man who established this attitude as a necessity within the Permanent Presidential Council was Maurer. His reasoning was solid and clear. He would have said: “Now Romania is personalized by Ceauºescu. Ceauºescu, by the nature of his function has to face all dangers confronting the country. We have to give him a bigger say, a bigger political force, to prove he has his back covered that he is assured, that there is no niche into the leadership of Romania, into the communist party, that someone could ever speculate to hit the positions promoted by Ceauºescu in the name of the party and of the country. This action imposes an obvious solidarity with Ceauºescu, an unconditioned support of his positions, a definition of these positions as totally expressing the party, the country, the people.”33 During this first period, 1965–1971, Ceauºescu succeeded to assure himself the popularity. The people saw in him the “providential man”, the leader restituing them the dignity, expressing their own hopes and dreams. They could not imagine that he would use this popularity to ease his way to a total accaparation of the power. And nothing, no one, has impeded the application of his plan. All started with the changes in the mechanism of power, operated at the 9th Congress of the party from 1965 when the Romanian Worker’s Party became the Romanian Communist * And those soon were silenced by propaganda and then by Security — author’s note, R.I. 76 RODICA IAMANDI 12 Party and Romanian Popular Republic became Romanian Socialist Replubic, when the congresses were re-numbered and a new constitution was adopted. At the Congress in 1969, and the following ones, the changes in the mechanism of power became much obvious, and more precisely aimed. Very important was the change of the name of the supreme function within the party, from secretary general of the C.C. of R.C.P., into that of secretary general of R.C.P. At the time he was already president of the Presidential Council and that was as I have said, the supreme function in state. From now on Ceauºescu was to be elected not by the plenary of C.C. but directly by the Congress of the party. Thus he became the only inamovable person in the party, protected under the simulacrum of party democracy. The measure affected the entire party, diminishing the importance and role of the other leadership organs, especially that of the Political Bureau to which even Dej has payed attention, because it used to be the main form of expression of the principle of collective leadership. Otherwise Ceauºescu himself declared the importance of this principle at the 9th Congress, as supreme principle of party leadership34. He defied elementary norms of party democracy. He arrived to be elected by a show were simply hands were risen and then cheers would fall unceasingly. Mind that the choice of the delegates at a Congress as such was preceeded by a carefull staff selection, monitored by Ceauºescu himself and with time, by Elena Ceauºescu, his wife, head of the terrible “Cabinet no. 2”. Even more, now, all the members of C.C. were from the ranks of these same delegates, to complete the image of a grotesque show. Ceauºescu’s thirst for power grew bigger in time. When he has visited China and North Coreea in 1971 he was seduced by the dimensions and by the forms of manifestation of the cult of personality there. He saw meetings of adulation of the leader, fascinating spectacles of light and sound and decided to import more of such a political and cultural system. “In Romania we are in error in what concerns the matter of the cult of personality, says Dumitru Popescu. As it is commented upon now is seems that it consisted of festive events only*. For Ceauºescu festivism was totally unsatisfactory and lame, much less than what he wanted. “A few voices singing osana were small potatoes. He was way beyond such tiny satisfactions. He would look over the newspapers, find phrases with eulogy and not be thrilled at all. For him, essential was the mass hysteria, millions’osana, over-enthuziastical collectives’adhesion, the rumble of the meetings in the public square, the huge crows of workers with their arms streched to reach him, the live ques anlong his car rides for kilometers, the scanning from hundreds chests. He has built as a lucid and calculated architect the complicated frame of mass delirium (...) He has organised periodically gigantic congresses and conferrences. He has institutionalized the grand country tours, the pompous work visits in the counties, plants, towns, villages and the so-called dialogue with the people were hundreds of thousands participated.”35 Thus, in a second phase, 1971–1980, Romania gets a “minicultural revolution” leading to the oversized cult of personality. After assuming the function of supreme * Although it may be considered an excuse — the note of the author, R.I. 13 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 77 commander of the armed forces he transforms the un-prestiged Political Bureau into the Political Executiv Committee controlling politically the activity of the government. I. Gh. Maurer, head of the government faces Ceauºescu’s acts with ever greater difficulty. His successors will have a solely decorative role. After 1974 Elena Ceauºescu launches herself into politics and gains one leadership function after the other, up to “prime vice-primeminister”. At this time, Ceauºescu’s controll over all acts of internal and external politics is entire. Differences start to show, in matters of form and content, especially from Maurer’s part, but his honorable attitude is not followed as an example by many others. Therefore, many politicians oposing imposture and megalomania of Ceauºescu’s political, social and economic life leave their functions “willingly” or are set aside. The “shadow directors” of such personality cult set on stage congresses, public gatherings and homage shows, training impressively large masses, in a Chinese and North Coreean style. Masses almost never gather willingly. The “shadow directors” invent and intitutionalize all types of National Councils mimiting democracy, only to elect as their head with exaggerated pomp, Nicolae Ceauºescu. Finally, the plenary meeting of March 1974 proposes to the Great National Assembly the institution of the function of president of Romania and for that function is unanimously elected Nicolae Ceauºescu. Through this new function, Ceauºescu reaches the climax of political power, with 1974, the dictatorial régime stepping into a new historical phase. In only nine years he has become the most powerful man in Romania, “an absolute monarch”36, after Silviu Brucan, and the following association at power of his wife Elena Ceauºescu makes of Romanian a “communist two-headed monarchy”37. He succeeded to build an almost perfect model of a personal dictatorship political system, permitting him to control Romania, in every way, and the life of the 23 millions Romanians, as well, for almost a quarter of a century. The public opinion assisted perplexed to the metamorphosis of the leaders they put so many hopes in. He was the one who promised at the tribune of the 9th Congress not to admit “any forms of overstepping the principle of work and collective leadership”, and he has as well proposed the introduction of procedure in conformity to which “no party member can have more that one function of leadership, either within the party or within the state”38. During the period that entered history as the “Golden Epoch” or as “Nicolae Ceauºescu Epoch”, shaped into form after 1971, the cult of personality gathers the most absurd forms of expression and the totalitarian power is finally consecrated, as a direct consequence of this cult. Any act of internal or external policy is under the thumb of the general secretary, any action takes place under his “direct supervision and guidance”, given his “pretious indications” — expressions obsessively usual with party propadanda of the epoch. At the same time, a cult of personality of Elena Ceauºescu was carefully installed, motivated by her alledgedlly exceptional merits during the revolutionary times in Romania. Like it was not important that Ceauºescu himself has asked from the tribune of the 9th Congress the objective presentation of the place and role of any personality in history. He considered damaging “the exaggeration of the merits of some 78 RODICA IAMANDI 14 militants”. “No leader, no matter how proeminent, said Ceauºescu then, cannot be preented as the only agent of the historical events, without deifying that person, to denying the role of the masses, of the people… Would be wrong to exaggerate past merits of some leaders only to put the history ‘in accord’* with the present.”39 With the demagogy characteristic for his political discourse at this time, he said after the plenary meeting of 1968, that in the activity of any party member to start from “an objective and lucid analysis of the facts and not from the myths. We do not need idols. We do not need to transform people into flags”40. Bending the historical truth, party propaganda has put into circulation facts and appreciations over the limit of the verosimility ment to create an hero aura for Nicolae Ceauºescu, to increase his domestic and foreign prestige. In reality propaganda harmed as none of the following were believable: the presence of Nicolae Ceauºescu, aged 12 into the revolutionary movement, at 15 in the party, or his important contribution to the activity of the National Anti-Fascist Committee (1933) and the arrangement of the 1st of May 1939 demonstration with Elena Ceauºescu, or even the episode of his presence in the forced camp at Târgu Jiu… In direct relation to the development of the communist totalitarianism is the proliferation of the cult of personality of Nicolae Ceauºescu and in the 80s the cult of personality of Elena Ceauºescu, to grotesque formes of expression. Thanks to a perfect functioning propaganda mechanism and to a rhetoric overstating the merits of the secretary general, forcing the superlatives of the Romanian language over decent limits, the cult flourished. No less useful proving to be the actions of renamed artists, writers, plastic artists, who, from conviction or opportunism made all possible to set him high on a pedestal of power. Thanks to those as well Ceauºescu believed himsefl that he is the “Carpathians’genius”, that the history of this people begins and ends with him. “The newpapers, said in 1983 Vlad Georgescu, one of the opponents of the régime from abroad, see him as ‘the icon of a prince’, referring to him as ‘Man’, written with capital letter, as once was written ‘God’ with capital letter and they use formula ‘his people’ as it was used with the kings, but no prince or king in Romania, not even those with the biggest egos did not arrive at these unnatural forms of expressions, none practiced to such an extent their cult or their families’cult. Only Stalin has been genius and profet and father of many nations.”41 The appropriation and manipulation of the national and patriotic feeling, invoking obstinately the historical past under the pretext that it restitutes to the people the true national dignity were diversions in the service of the cult of personality. The festive meetings the pompous festive shows to alledgedlly honour the actions of the forefathers were just pretexts to inoculate into the public opinion the idea that R.C.P. was in fact the person continuing the traditions of fight for social justice, independence and national sovereignity of the Romanian people. By relationship, as relatives, the secretary general, personifies all the aspirations of Romanians. It came to the point were the name and figure of Nicolae Ceauºescu were situated next to legendary symbols of Romanian history * Author’s underline. 15 THE CULT PERSONALITY IN ROMANIA, DURING COMMUNISM 79 — from Burebista to Decebal, Bãlcescu and Cuza. From here to associating the party and Ceauºescu with the name of the country in a popular slogan of “the golden epoch”, “the party, Ceauºescu, Romania”, was just a step. Within such a context it is easy to understand that any criticism to dictatorship and to the cult of personality, or directed to the absurd economic and social policies was immidiately qualified as anti-Romanian and sanctioned as such by the opressive régime. Without any doubt, the cult of personality carefully cultivated was supported by a wise foreign policy, of independence and sovereignity. Such foreign policies were aproved by all Western powers, as well, since the principles of these policies were most of them part of Helsinki Treaty. Mind that many were the same as those formulated by Dej in Declaration of April 1964. Thus the president of Romania, speculating the games of Western leaders, came to consider himself (due to so many mouthpieces, as well) one of the great personalities of the contemporary world. A retrospective view on the last quarter of century of communism rises the question of possibility for this absurd cult of personality of Ceauºescu and his despotic régime, especially after the sad experience of Dej. Such a state of things that brought Romania on the brink of disaster was born at the confluence of three factors: the stalinist model, the will of the leader and the either active or pasive acceptance of the population42. The active support was offered by the communist higher activists (“the nomenclature”), mainly the admierers and councils always surounding Ceauºescu and local activists. The passive support was offered by the resigned, humble or indiferent masses, in front of dictatorial decisions even when those were not in their best interest, affecting their hopes and their human dignity and freedom. The stand up reaction was almost inexistent, not to be explained by cowardice attitude, but rather by a temporarily compromise, given that the cult of personality and the dictatorship both were considered temporary by their fragility, artificiality, demagogy and lack of truth. Ceauºescu has a syncretic nature, combining elements of the cult of Mussolini and Hitler, Mao and Kim Ir Sen (weaving in the same fabric the Asian traditional elements of cult, with the Sovietic elements of the cult of personality)43. NOTES 1. Sergiu Tãmaº, Dicþionar politic. Instituþiile democraþiei ºi cultura civicã, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei Române, 1993. 2. *** Dicþionar enciclopedic, vol. I, A.C., Bucureºti, Editura Enciclopedicã, 1993. 3. Ovidiu Trãsnea, Nicolae Kallos (coord.), Micã enciclopedie de politologie, Bucureºti, Editura ªtiinþificã ºi Enciclopedicã, 1977, pp. 111–112. 4. O.G. Drobniþki, I.S. Kon (coord.), Mic dicþionar de eticã, Moscova, Editura de Stat pentru Literaturã Politicã, 1965, pp. 25–26 (C). 5. Ibidem. 6. N.S. Khrushchev, Raportul de activitate al Comitetului Central al Partidului Comunist al Uniunii Sovietice la Congresul al XX-lea al Partidului, Bucureºti, Editura de Stat pentru Literaturã Politicã, 1956, p. 134. 7. “Discursul secret” of Khrushchev at the 20th Congress of CPSU, immediately taken over in the western press, and in Tariq Ali, The Stalinist Legacy, Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1984, pp. 256–270, apud Vladimir Tismãneanu, Reinventarea politicului. Europa rãsãriteanã de la Stalin la Havel, Iaºi, Polirom, 1997 and A. Rossi, Autopsie du stalinisme, Paris, 1957, apud Raymond Aron, Democraþie ºi totalitarism, Bucureºti, Editura ALL Educaþional, 2001, pp. 204–220. 80 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. RODICA IAMANDI Vladimir Tismãneanu, op.cit., p. 74. Raymond Aron, op. cit., p. 194. Ibidem, p. 212. Ibidem, p. 219. A. Rossi, Autopsie du stalinisme, Paris, 1957, p. 10, apud Raymond Aron, op. cit., p. 209. R. Aron, op. cit., p. 211. Apud Roy Medvedev, Despre Stalin ºi Stalinism, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 1991, p. 56. Ibidem, p. 133. Victor Frunzã, Istoria stalinismului în România, Bucureºti, Editura Humanitas, 1990, p. 491. Ibidem. Silviu Brucan, Generaþia irositã, Bucureºti, Editura Univers&Calistrat Hogaº, 1992, p. 59. Gheorghiu-Dej, Darea de seamã a delegaþiei P.M.R. la cel de-al XX-lea Congres al P.C.U.S., în: “Scânteia”, anul XXXI, nr. 5371, 7 decembrie, 1961, p. 1. Florin Constantiniu, O istorie sincerã a poporului român, Bucureºti, Editura Univers Enciclopedic, 1997, p. 471. Not after long, Vasile Luca was arrested, trailed and at 10th October 1954, sentenced to his death, sentence changed after the appeal, to a sentence for life. “Scânteia”, anul XXI, nr. 2360, 29 mai, 1952, p. 1. Victor Frunzã, op. cit., p. 423. Silviu Brucan, op. cit., p. 95. Dumitru Popescu, Am fost ºi cioplitor de himere, Bucureºti, Editura Expres, 1994, p. 50. Ibidem op. cit., p. 153. Gh. Gheorghiu-Dej, op. cit., p. 1. Ibidem. Nicolae Ceauºescu, Cuvântare la adunarea activului de partid al municipiului Bucureºti, 26 IV 1968. 16 30. Victor Frunzã, op. cit., p. 459, 461. 31. Dumitru Popescu, op. cit., p. 133. 32. Nicolae Ceauºescu, România pe drumul desãvârºirii construcþiei socialiste, vol. III, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1969, p. 194. 33. Dumitru Popescu, op. cit., p. 153. 34. Nicolae Ceauºescu, România pe drumul desãvârºirii construcþiei socialiste, vol. I, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1968, p. 74. 35. Dumitru Popescu, op. cit., p. 234. 36. Silviu Brucan, op. cit., p. 145. 37. Florin Constantiniu, op. cit., p. 515. 38. Nicolae Ceauºescu, op. cit., vol. I, p. 74. 39. Ibidem, p. 337. 40. Nicolae Ceauºescu, România pe drumul desãvârºirii construcþiei socialiste, vol. III, Bucureºti, Editura Politicã, 1969, p. 194. 41. Vlad Georgescu, Politicã ºi istorie. Cazul comuniºtilor români 1944–1977, München, Jon Dumitru Verlag, 1983, p. 91. 42. Florin Constantiniu, op. cit., p. 516. 43. See Lavinia Betea, Psihologie politicã. Individ, lider, mulþime în regimul comunist, Iaºi, Polirom, 2001, pp. 176–177, 188–190, for a development of this argument, as for a competent identification and analysis of the propaganda directions that have built the cult of personality of Nicolae Ceauºescu: the falsifying of biography, the identification of the leader with the party, the people and the country, the appropriation of the mission of the “saviour” of the nation, the appropriation of the role of a visionary and unrested guide for the destiny of the masses, the appropriation of the status of an international politician. ARGUMENTS AND POINTS OF VIEW REPRESENTATION OF HISTORY AS CONFLICT PREVENTION STRATEGY. ARGUMENTS FOR A RESEARCH AGENDA LUCIAN JORA Within the international system most countries tend to view the EU as a trade giant. In a lesser extent EU is considered as a valuable model of regional integration and security community. A potential research agenda would examine the EU as an integration model and security community in relation with East Asia (Japan, China, Korea, ASEAN) and the Middle East, with the major prospects for regional cooperation. On the case of EU the regional political agenda among the member states was followed by programs and projects design to implement it at the grass roots level within the member state societies. Sometimes it succeeded to achieve the wanted results and sometimes not. However, during the years European Commission accumulated trough the implemented projects a valuable experience. This experience may be useful for the implementation of the East Asian policies of reconciliation and regional integration. As a known example, the events of World War II continue to divide many parts of the world, because each country memorializes the period differently. These contrasting ways of remembering can be observed in World War II museums, schoolbooks, etc. throughout the region. Would be useful to assemble data on how war and peace museums and history school books in key, representative countries for a particular regional system have chosen to portray this controversial period and to compare them with the data in key European Union countries, France, Germany, UK. On this sense the European accumulated experience may be used to reveal the way in which zones of fracture and conflicts in can be presented not only in their often-dramatic historical authenticity, but also in terms of their contributions to the identity of different nations1. As a general hypothesis we may say that the cultural presence with a display of nationality as a label is no longer the exclusive precinct of national governments and their agencies. It occurs widely, driven by all types of transnational interests, emanating from politics, economy, education, science, culture and civil society, in a diversity of exchanges and collaborative forms. The trends towards globalization and localization are increasing the complexity of this trend. Teaching history in a certain manner can be a tool for encouraging students to be critical, and think Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 81–85, Bucharest, 2005. 82 LUCIAN JORA 2 about how they can tolerate a plurality of views about what is right and what is wrong. This is essential in creating security communities at the grass roots level. As general theoretic background research themes we propose the following: The Process of Reconciliation: From Diplomatic to Educational Initiatives; The challenges to teach tolerance towards historical enemies; The Impact of Democratic Development on Contested History2. Having in mind the European approach we are meant to ask and find answers to the questions like: What constitutes the local national approach? How does one interpret the historic heritage in local national terms? What constitutes the basis for a plural reading of the city and its history in the European versus the local extra-European respective case? The suitable techniques dedicated to bring the historic heritage and experience of a particular country to the world; what is the place represented by academia as source of public policy initiative involving the representation of history? Having in mind that trough the European Heritage Days, efforts have been made to propose subjects common to many countries at the same time (heritage and society, industrial heritage, etc.). Equally important are the means to insure visibility and social impact for the research findings For instance we consider that cultural discourse must connect with economic, political and media discourses or risk being ignored by the decision makers. The link between culture (representation of history) and development is not yet properly studied. I hope to set up the foundations for a research agenda on this crucial connection. Within the present research it may apply by finding ways to integrate the academic approach of historians with the contemporary approach of cultural industries and public policies. The convergence of culture and trade interests is leading to new relationships between cultural institutes and the private sector, though many annalists are considering unclear whether this new agenda will impact adversely on cooperation between the institutes or other national players3. Equally important are the means to insure visibility and social impact for the research findings For instance we consider once more that cultural discourse must connect with economic, political and media discourses or risk being ignored by the decision makers. For example the use of cultural investments for increasing the prestige and for improving international image of a place are methods currently applied by cities like Paris, Barcelona, Frankfurt, Bilbao, etc. Analyzing the connection between the cultural infrastructure and development in East Asia may reveal a way to insure visibility for the theoretical findings which otherwise are usually ignored by the decision makers. The research results will be the raw material to design a project design submitted first to further universities and then to international organizations of the region. Once agreed at the international level those structures may persuade the national structures toward concrete national policies regarding cultural and educational initiatives. The same research agenda need to debate the medium of representation. In our historiographic practices, we are inclined to use visual images as a 3 REPRESENTATION OF HISTORY AS CONFLICT PREVENTION STRATEGY 83 complement of our written discourse, rather than as components of a discourse in its own right, by means of which we might be able to say something different from and other than what we can say in verbal form. We are inclined to use pictures primarily as “illustrations” of the predications made in our verbally written discourse. We have not on the whole exploited the possibilities of using images as a principal medium of discursive representation, using verbal commentary only diacritically, that is to say, to direct attention to, specify, and emphasize a meaning conveyable by visual means alone. Some things — the cites landscapes, sounds, strong emotions, certain kinds of conflicts between individuals and groups, collective events and the movements of crowds — can be better represented on film (and, we might add, video) than in any merely verbal account. “Better” here would mean not only with greater verisimilitude or stronger emotive effect but also less ambiguously, more accurately. Every written history is a product of processes of condensation, displacement, symbolization, and qualification exactly like those used in the production of a filmed representation. It is only the medium that differs, not the way in which messages are produced. As a theoretic model we rely on the concept first pioneered by Karl Deutsch and developed nowadays by Emanuel Adler: security communities4. Basically a security community is a regional system, where trough continuous dialog, diplomacy, communication, shared prosperity, common economic interests, the military means to settle an interstate dispute become unthinkable. The European Community was design as a security community. It started as a mean to prevent a further war between France and Germany trough common economic interests, mutual control over the strategic industries and regional integration. The success of EC as a model of regional integration and security community determined leading scholars to examine security communities in various historical and regional contexts: in places where they exist, where they are emerging, and where they are hardly detectable. This kind of approach is based on the constructivist theory. It is an approach to international relations, security and development studies opposite to Hans Morgenthau Realist approach. It may prove more suitable to the 21st century international system. Within the study the terms memory and historical memory are used interchangeably to mean the manner in which the past is socially interpreted: Such memories are communicated via all manner of cultural products, including programmatic political statements, popular journalism, film, literature, high art, as well as historiography itself. Ultimately, they contribute to the self-identification of individuals, together or as separate groups. The term Representation of History (see Graphic ) is understood as the way we use to valorize the products of historical research to the general public. It is a matter of skills, and specific lobby with cultural, politic and economic implications. After all any historic fact is a complexity and the manner a historian represent it to the public may create bridges of communication, or grow enemies. 84 LUCIAN JORA Culture Representation of History 4 5 REPRESENTATION OF HISTORY AS CONFLICT PREVENTION STRATEGY 85 NOTES 1. Interarts and EFAH, Study on Cultural Cooperation in Europe — June 2003. See also: Report on cultural cooperation in the European Union, 2000/2323(INI), Committee on Culture, Youth, Education, the Media and Sport, Rapporteur: Giorgio Ruffolo, 2001. 2. Related research projects active at the present or recently finished: – Carnegie Council on Ethics and International Affairs, The History and the Politics of Reconciliation Program. – Laura Hein and Mark Selden, In Censoring History: Citizenship and Memory in Japan, Germany and the United States, M.E. Sharpe, 2000. – Takashi Yoshida (Western Michigan University), History Education and Reconciliation: The Choice between Examining Japanese Wartime Aggression and Revitalizing Nationalism; Remembering the Pacific War WWII Museums in China, Japan, South Korea, and Taiwan. – Roland Bleiker (University of Queensland), and Yong-ju Hoang (Pusan University of Foreign Studies): From Confrontation to Cooperation in the Two Koreas, The Role of History Education in Promoting Reconciliation. – Carolyn Kissane (Columbia University), Lessons from the Classrooms of Kazakhstan: Teaching Reconciliation and Understanding in a Time of Transition. – Alison Kitson (University of Warwick), History Textbooks in Northern Ireland. – Thomas D. Sherlock (United States Military Academy), Secondary School History Texts: The Case of Russia. 3. MKW Wirtschaftsforschung GmbH, Exploitation and development of the job potential in the cultural sector in the age of digitalisation, Brussels, Directorate-General for Employment and Social Affairs, European Commission, 2001. For the entire problematic see also:European Parliament, opinion on the communication from the Commission entitled Cohesion policy and culture:a contribution to employment, rapporteur. L. Vecchio, p.8, PE 222.345. 4. Emanuel Adler, Michael N Barnett (editors), Security communities, London, Cambridge University Press, 1998. CULIANU IN ITALIA ROBERTA MORETTI Le tappe italiane L’Italia ha avuto un posto speciale nella vita e nell’itinerario intellecttuale di Ioan P. Culianu. I suoi studi sulla gnosi sono legati al periodo trascorso come borsista all’Università Cattolica di Milano (1973–1976), dove segue le lezioni di Ugo Bianchi. Il trasferimento in Olanda, dal 1976 al 1986, non aveva interrotto il dialogo con amici, colleghi e alcuni editori italiani. In Italia aveva pubblicato la monografia su Mircea Eliade (Cittadella, Assisi, 1978), e i seguenti altri libri: Gnosticismo e pensiero moderno: Hans Jonas (L’Erma di Bretschneider, Roma, 1985), Religione e potere (Marietti, Torino, 1981), Iter in Silvis (Sfameni, Messina, 1981). E se le opere successive: Expériences de l’extase (Payot, Parigi 1984), Eros et Magie à la Renaissance, 1484 (Flammarion, Parigi, 1984), Les gnoses dualistes d’Occident (Payot, Parigi, 1987) usciranno in Francia e Out of This World in USA, (Shambhala, Boston, 1991), esse avranno non di meno edizioni italiane. Alcuni intellettuali e studiosi italiani cominciarono ad accorgersi di Culianu abbastanza presto. Elémire Zolla negli anni Settanta lo notò come autore di alcuni articoli specialistici, quei testi — scrive — “mi imponevano una ressa di quesiti: il tono era di chi ha accumulato una conoscenza vastissima e quindi opera sulle varie questioni religiose ordinandone gli elementi con calma infinita e anche con un sottile divertimento”1. Eros e magia nel Rinascimento aveva ottenuto, come riconosce Paola Zambelli, studiosa della scuola fiorentina di E. Garin, un “notevole successo”, anche se le tesi di Culianu di rado venivano condivise2. Anche P.O. Kristeller, l’autorevole specialista americano di studi sul Rinascimento, si era accorto di quell’opera di Culianu. Nell’edizione riveduta de Il pensiero filosofico di Marsilio Ficino3, Kristeller cita nella bibliografia Eros e Magia nel Rinascimento dopo averne consultate le versioni inglese e francese. Né gli fu ignota la prima tesi di laurea (non pubblicata) che Culianu discusse a Bucarest nel 1972. Un altro attento autore italiano di Culianu era stato Giovanni Casadio, docente di storia delle religioni all’Università di Salerno. Autore, tra l’altro, di “Vie gnostiche all’immortalità” (Morcelliana, Brescia, 1997). Nell’articolo Ricordo di Ioan Petru Culianu (1950–1991) pubblicato nel n. 16 di “Religioni e Società” (maggio-agosto 1993), Casadio sottolinea il riavvicinarsi dello studioso romeno all’Italia: “Dal 1987 — scrive Casadio — riprendono — e diventano Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 86–96, Bucharest, 2005. 2 CULIANU IN ITALIA 87 progressivamente sempre più stretti — i rapporti con l’Italia, il paese, in fondo al quale il nostro è spiritualmente più legato, dopo la patria rumena”4. Il legame speciale con l’Italia è ribadito da L.E. Sullivan quando dice: (Culianu) “amava l’Italia, anche se le circostanze difficili, in cui ºi dibatté, lo fecero soffrire... Per lui però Italia era anche il posto dove era stato ben accolto, in cui aveva potuto riprendere gli studi. L’Italia era la «casa» dei pensieri per cui nutriva più ammirazione, Ficino, Bruno ed altri esponenti del Rinascimento occulto fiorentino... Penso che le sequenze storiche che maggiormente lo interessavano, anche dal punto di vista dell’immaginazione letteraria erano italiane... L’Italia era stata per lui come una porta, che ha attraversato per entrare in un mondo altro, un luogo di passaggio per entrare in altre dimensioni”5. Nel 1987 Culianu e Hillary passarono due settimane nella città di Firenze visitando i monumenti. Culianu era già stato a Firenze quindici anni prima quando arrivò per la prima volta in Italia con la borsa di studio per seguire i corsi all’Università per stranieri di Perugia. Per lo studioso romeno Firenze aveva una forte valenza d’anima, riflessa nei suoi studi sul Rinascimento, una città che alimentava altresì la sua immaginazione narrativa. Ted Anton in Eros, Magic, and the Murder of Professor Culianu (Northwestern, 1996, p. 149 ss.) scrive che “per Culianu, Firenze era prima di tutto, la città di Sandro Botticelli, l’artista le cui sculture e pitture celebravano la potenza delle dee. Ioan e Hillary — scrive Anton — ritornarono più volte agli Uffizi per vedere La Primavera di Botticelli...”. Secondo Anton, Culianu condivideva con Botticelli l’ossessione per le figure di dee, e Hillary, dallo studioso innamorato veniva associata alla Venere botticelliana. Casadio, a sua volta, ricorda la “visita-lampo a Firenze nel gennaio 1987 [che Culianu fece] per familiarizzarsi con i luoghi dove voleva ambientare il suo secondo romanzo (inedito), una sorta di giallo che narra delle oscure trame che al tempo del Savonarola «cercano di cancellare l’immagine della bellezza, di distruggere un quadro del Botticelli»...”6 Nel 1989 quando Culianu è professore all’Università di Chicago, riceve un invito da Grazia Marchianò dell’Università di Siena per un giro di conferenze. La prima nel febbraio 1989 alla biblioteca di Palazzo Pretorio ad Arezzo. Il tema concordato è La sacralità femminile; il secondo incontro è a Siena dove parla su La magia del Tasso; a Roma nel Dipartimento di Letterature Comparate tiene una lezione sull’esoterismo nell’opera di Carlos Castaneda; a Firenze all’Istituto Stensen dialoga con Zolla sull’eredità di Eliade; ad Assisi nella libreria “Oriente e Occidente” illustra il pensiero di Mircea Eliade. Alla Facoltà di Lettere di Siena l’invito gli viene da Sandro Briosi (m. 1998), che Culianu aveva conosciuto all’Università di Groninga, dove Briosi insegnava prima di ricevere l’incarico di professore di letteratura italiana a Siena. Informato da Grazia Marchianò dell’arrivo di Culianu gli chiede di tenere una conferenza su La magia nel Tasso. Le due conferenze ad Arezzo e ad Assisi furono registrate in due cassette audio da 60 minuti e ci è stato perciò possibile ascoltarle. 88 ROBERTA MORETTI 3 In entrambe le conferenze Ioan Petru Culianu è introdotto da Marchianò. Ad Arezzo era venuto ad ascoltare Culianu Ugo Bianchi e ad Assisi era presente E. Zolla. Nella conferenza di Assisi (12 febbraio 1989), Mircea Eliade e il suo pensiero, G. Marchianò ricordava quando anni indietro si era imbattuta nel nome di Culianu, a proposito dell’articolo: La femme céleste et son ombre, pubblicato su “Numen” 23 (1976): “Ricordo che mi colpì questo studioso e mi chiesi chi potesse essere. Poi l’episodio si è eclissato nella mia mente, sono passati anni finché di recente, seppure non ricordi lo spunto immediato, scrissi a Culianu a Chicago proponendogli di venire in Italia per una serie di conferenze in varie università. Lui fu amabile e disponibilissimo: «Si mi capita di venire in Olanda in febbraio — le rispose —, si può senz’altro combinare».” Grazia Marchianò ad Assisi sottolineava alcuni aspetti della personalità di Eliade, e l’eredità intellettuale raccolta dal discepolo Ioan P. Culianu. Ad Arezzo il tema della Sacralità femminile è trattato da Culianu a partire da un dettaglio dell’abbigliamento della donna, la scarpa col tacco alto. Culianu fece scorrere delle diapositive su un gran numero di calzature femminili di molte epoche e tradizioni, e una certa sorpresa si diffuse in sala. Un taglio interpretativo di questo genere era nuovo al pubblico che lo ascoltava. Il Prof. Conci riconosceva che Culianu “ci ha mostrato come leggere oggetti, segni culturali in una chiave che francamente non la si riteneva prima di lui così idonea a mostrare antiche stratificazioni culturali”. Il Prof. Dini che, con Conci e altri colleghi, stava all’epoca effecttuando ricerche antropologiche nel territorio aretino, in particolare sulle matres locali, cercando di comprendere come certi elementi di origine arcaica tendono a riproporsi, era rimasto colpito dal modo in cui Culianu, aveva accostato “questa continuità sacrale attraverso certe immagini”. Le reazioni di altri furono critiche, a voltre polemiche. Tra gli intervenuti, la Dott.ssa Bertini, il Prof. Ricci, la Prof.ssa Tasinato, il Prof. Bucci, il Prof. Lieberg. Nel 1989 sulla rivista romana “Abstracta” esce un profilo di Mircea Eliade, nella serie “Invito alla lettura di...”, a cura di Grazia Marchianò7. Culianu tratteggia quelle che definisce le «sette anime» di Mircea Eliade e le sfaccettature della sua complessa personalità. Culianu scrive: “Profonda è in Eliade la convinzione che l’esperienza religiosa degli «specialisti del sacro» — lo yogin, lo sciamano, l’alchimista — è ripetuta da ognuno di noi, ma in modo incosciente”. Elémire Zolla ricordava il soggiorno italiano di Culianu in un articolo su “Panorama” (aprile 1989), quando i due studiosi avevano dialogato tra di loro. L’arrivo in Italia di I.P. Culianu aveva coinciso con l’uscita della versione italiana della tesi di Dottorato alla Sorbona: I Miti dei dualismi occidentali (Jaca Book, Milano, 1989), un’opera le cui conclusioni suscitarono qualche sconcerto, ma anche un’attenzione critica vibrante, come nel capitolo iniziale dell’opera Sugli orienti del pensiero di Grazia Marchianò, construito sul contrappunto tra mitologie dell’Occidente e mitologie dell’Oriente8. Nel 1989 Culianu parla sullo Gnosticismo all’Università «La Sapienza» di Roma su invito di Ugo Bianchi, e al congresso dell’AAR–SBL (American Academy of Religion – Society of Biblical Literature), tenutosi quell’anno ad 4 CULIANU IN ITALIA 89 Anaheim in California. Lo stesso anno tiene delle trasmissioni in romeno su Mircea Eliade per la BBC, ed è poi a Dublino per parlare della “Religione tra spiritualismo e la Fisica dei Quanti” e la “Religione come Sistema”. Il 1989 e 1990 sono gli anni più italiani della coppia Culianu – Wiesner. Nella primavera del 1990 Grazia Marchianò invita Culianu come professore a contratto per il trimestre dal 1° marzo al 1° giugno (A.A. 1989–1990), ad Arezzo dove tiene un seminario per la cattedra di Estetica. Il tema di questo ciclo di lezioni riguardava Faust: un mito alle radici dell’Occidente. Assegna esercitazioni sull’argomento a varie studentesse. Il suo italiano è fluente, i modi semplici e la naturale simpatia attenuano la soggezione di chi lo ascolta conquistato dalla sua erudizione. In febbraio esce un articolo su “Panorama” (n. 18, 1990), dal titolo E’morto il re — occhio all’erede, in cui Culianu analizza gli ultimi eventi della politica romena. Tiene altre conferenze: il 3 maggio è all’Università di Salerno su invito di M. Oldoni e R. Rusconi, dove parla delle Correnti dualistiche medievali; il 4 maggio è all’Istituto Suor Orsola Benincasa a Napoli, dove presenta insieme a la narratrice Elisabetta Rasy, Marchianò, Conci e Trione l’opera di Zolla, che era uscita nel febbraio del 1990: Verità segrete esposte in evidenza. Sincretismo e fantasia. Contemplazione e esotericità (Marsilio, Venezia)9. Il 1990 è un anno fervido di iniziative che nascono in territorio italiano. Marchianò e Culianu stilano un progetto che trae ispirazione dall’approssimarsi del centenario del “Parliament of Religions”10, in programma a Chicago nel 1993. Il progetto prevedeva una conferenza internazionale, una sorta di piccolo parlamento delle religioni in Italia, simmetrico al grande evento a Chicago. I due studiosi decidono di proporre il progetto all’allora direttore dell’Istituto Suor Orsola Benincasa di Napoli, il Prof. Villani. L’occasione fu data dalla presentazione del libro di E. Zolla tenuta dallo stesso Villani all’Istituto Suor Orsola. Quella stessa sera il progetto fu esposto a Villani, ma la sua reazione fu tiepida e non se ne fece nulla. Fu così persa l’occasione di ricordare in Italia un evento che negli Stati Uniti rappresentò un nodo cruciale nella storia delle religioni. (Traggo questi commenti da una conversazione con la Sig.ra Marchianò). Va invece a buon fine il progetto di un volume per i sessantacinque anni di Elémire Zolla. Grazia Marchianò ne parla a Culianu che accetta con entusiasmo di contribuire con un suo saggio11. L’editore Red di Como accetta di pubblicarlo. Culianu ne incontra il Direttore Rosenberg Colorni in occasione della partecipazione a un incontro con Roberto Calasso e Michele Placido alla Fiera del Libro a Torino (maggio 1990). Nel giugno del’90 esce un altro articolo su “Panorama” dal titolo La realtà? Sono due. La rivista “Abstracta”, n. 50 (luglio-agosto ’90), pubblica il racconto breve dal titolo Il pentimento tardivo di Horemheb, già pubblicato negli Stati Uniti sulla “Harvard Review”. Anche questo racconto viene concepito durante un viaggio con Hillary al Cairo, a Gerusalemme e in Spagna. Hillary all’epoca preparava la sua tesi di dottorato a Harvard sulla filosofia di al-Kindi. Un altro racconto breve esce su “Leggere” (n. 18/1990) si intitola La Sequenza Segreta, ed è presentato da E. Zolla. In America La Sequenza Segreta esce sulla “New 90 ROBERTA MORETTI 5 York Review of Science Fiction”, con una simpatica presentazione di poche righe di Hillary Wiesner. Questi due anni italiani sono ricordati anche dall’amico Giovanni Casadio, il quale osserva come essi vedano “anche il saldarsi del suo sodalizio con un maestro del paradosso come Zolla, al quale lo legavano da tempo affinità elettive e che può del resto considerarsi il suo terzo mentore dopo Eliade e Bianchi...12” Casadio ricorda anche un saggio di Grazia Marchianò in cui i due studiosi sono messi a confronto: Le aure di un tempo concluso in La religione della terra13. Molti impegni aspettano Culianu negli USA dopo il periodo italiano: le lezioni alla Divinity School, i progetti concordati con Eliade da portare a termine, l’avvio della rivista “Incognita”, la pubblicazione dei Miti dei dualismi occidentali in versione americana, e un altro libro, l’ultimo, su i viaggi ultraterreni in una prospettiva comparativa. Murato nel suo appartamento a Chicago — dove nell’inverno del 1990–1991 aveva subito il furto del computer — Culianu scrive fino a notte fonda. Le telefonate con la fidanzata a Harvard gli danno fugaci momenti felici. Di giorno lavora alla Divinity School, gli studenti si affollano nel suo studio al terzo piano. Sembra che nella primavera del 1991 ricevesse minacce di morte. Ne parla distrattamente con Hillary, ma prosegue per la sua strada fino a quel 21 di maggio. Verso le ore 19,30 ora italiana, Grazia Marchianò, ancora nel suo studio ad Arezzo, riceve una telefonata da E. Zolla che le riferisce di una chiamata di un amico da Chicago: Giovanni Culianu è stato assassinato. Il 5 giugno del 1991, anche all’Università di Arezzo si commemorava la figura di Ioan Petru Culianu: “Caro Preside — scriveva Marchianò al Prof. D.A. Conci — Ioan P. Culianu, Professore di Storia delle Religioni all’Università di Chicago, fondatore e direttore della rivista «Incognita», ...studioso illustre del mondo accademico internazionale, è morto il 21 maggio a Chicago, come riferito nella stampa nazionale e internazionale. Aneva 41 anni. Culianu è stato professore a contratto presso la Cattedra di Estetica, nella nostra Facoltà nel trimestre marzo-giugno 1990. Suggerisco che nel prossimo Consiglio di Facoltà del 5 giugno, la Sua figura venga brevemente ricordata, e un minuto di silenzio sia osservato alla Sua memoria”. La conferenza aretina di Culianu La conferenza sul tema “La sacralità femminile”, illustrata da varie diapositive, si svolse nella sede della Biblioteca Comunale di Arezzo ai primi di febbraio 1989 nell’ambito dei “Colloqui interdisciplinari di Estetica”, organizzati presso la Biblioteca dalla Prof.ssa Marchianò. Da Roma vennero ad ascoltare il Prof. Culianu, il Prof. Ugo Bianchi, col quale Culianu si era rilaureato alla Cattolica di Milano, la Signora Bianchi e il Prof. Giovanni Casadio. Alla trascrizione del testo, facciamo precedere un breve commento. Culianu dirige il suo sguardo sulla semiotica del corpo femminile e con perizia e pazienza, rintraccia i “camuffamenti” moderni di una sacralità antica di millenni. 6 CULIANU IN ITALIA 91 Una sacralità che investe il corpo femminile, un tempo venerato per la sua forza creatrice, associato alla terra madre, fecondata dalle piogge e dall’aratro, e immagine della fertilità. Questo tipo di sacralità, e insieme ad essa la figura femminile, è però mutata con le varie culture e epoche che si sono traversate. Culianu osserva il percorso dell’immagine femminile nella storia, a partire dalle veneri steatopigie (dai grandi fianchi) fino alle modelle di Vogue con corsetti, rossetti e tacchi. Dopo il Cinque-Seicento “la sacralità femminile — dice Culianu — compie un passo, per così dire, miracoloso, scende completamente in terra coinvolgendo la stessa donna; coinvolgendola nel sacro più che nel passato”. Culianu si riferisce qui ad un meccanismo complesso che non sembrerebbe coinvolgere nessuna sacralità, ma invece — dice — “ci porta quanto mai vicino alla dimensione sacrale perché ci spiega come essa si formi e nasca”. L’uomo moderno “areligioso” si libera del sacro diventando un soggetto che interviene in modo attivo nella storia. Culianu esamina qui un aspetto di questa libertà manifesto nella figura femminile depurata dall’idea che per millenni le era stata associata di incarnare una “ierofania della vita”. La sacralità femminile è dunque soggetta a mutamento, il fatto che non riusciamo più a riconoscere e decifrare i segni ierofanici non significa però che essi siano scomparsi. In un articolo su Abstracta (marzo, 1989), Culianu scriveva che “sebbene la oerofania sia in un certo senso intemporale, essa conosce mutamenti a seconda del tipo di cultura materiale di cui si tratta... Primordiali e fuori da ogni condizionamento culturale sembrano essere lo «spazio» e il «tempo» sacri, vale a dire la visione sacrale dello spazio e del tempo”. La sacralità femminile sarebbe cambiata dal momento in cui la donna, liberata dalle funzioni misteriose legate alla vita e alla morte, scende dal piano divino nel proprio corpo. L’espressione della sua autonomia si manifesterebbe nell’ambiguità del monstrum, una combinazione di forme che, specifica Culianu, si riscontrano già nel mondo antico14, soprattutto tra uomo e animale. Ed è proprio nella combinazione del corpo umano con il corpo equino che Culianu rintraccia un aspetto rilevante probabilmente all’origine dell’apparizione della moda del tacco alto. Culianu nella sua conferenza sottolinea un fatto inquietante: che la sacralità “scende ora nel corpo femminile come se questo non fosse altro che un’astrazione la cui realtà è negoziabile”. L’ipotesi che la realità sia negoziabile e prenda forma mediante astrazioni (l’idea del corpo è un’astrazione), sposta la questione sul processo mentale. Sono le idee a generare la realtà, ed essa è quanto mai instabile, mutevole, e soprattutto il prodotto delle nostre menti: “Non esiste un concetto di realtà stabile — dice Culianu — la realtà la facciamo noi, la producono le nostre menti... non esiste un corpo di donna ma esiste uno strumento la cui realtà è negoziabile, nel senso che lo si può cambiare e rendere visualmente diverso in sommo grado, e in varie epoche lo si è fatto e in modi molto diversi”. La donna è un’astrazione che cangia a seconda della cultura materiale in cui è inserita e a seconda delle idee che l’hanno generata. A seconda della cultura da 92 ROBERTA MORETTI 7 cui è pensata, prende forma, si modella, si mostra. Il concetto di sacralità in questi termini sembra perdersi, ma non è di questo parere Culianu che invece sottolinea il lato oscuro, complesso e ambiguo della donna. Il suo significato, dice Culianu, “è talmente intricato da essere stato trascurato finora quasi del tutto”. Perciò decifrarlo non è facile, e richiede un’immensa pazienza. Il tacco non è che un aspetto di questa transformazione, un segno la cui dimensione profonda è sacrale, il suo aspetto è sfuggente e occorre una sensibilità tutta speciale per coglierne i tratti. L’attenzione spostata sul processo mentale permette di cogliere la potenza generatrice e creativa della realtà. L’immaginazione solitamente considerata un ingrediente letterario, viene in tal modo ad agire su un aspetto delle realtà comune e ordinaria: l’abbigliamento e la sua dinamica sociale, la moda. Culianu nella sua esposizione si addentra decisamente a fondo in questo fenomeno. “La sacralità femminile non appartiene solo al passato ma si trova letteralmente in mezzo a noi, ovunque ci sia almeno un essere umano, quale che sia il suo sesso, ma comunque consapevole dell’esistenza dell’altro sesso. La sacralità femminile appartiene alla struttura del mondo perché non c’è un mondo senza di noi, e se noi non ci fissimo, non ci sarebbe alcun mondo15. La sacralità femminile, in quanto relazione dinamica, credo non si possa definire come un fatto (ted. Tatsache), ma tutt’al più come un accadere (ted. Geschehen). Penso inoltre che essa faccia parte della costituzione del mondo ad un titolo paragonabile a quello dell’elemente idrogeno, carbone o zolfo. Una sacralità femminile allo stato puro non esiste: essa è volatile, sfuggente, non la si ritrova se non in combinazioni e perciò descriverla è innanzitutto il mestiere dello storico. Ma siccome, non sempre fortunatamente, lo storico è un mestierante, neanche un bricoleur ma un mestierante, un collezionista di scatole vuote e di cicche già spente, può non sapere dove rivolgersi per trovarla. (...) Come loro forse sanno, in un suo celebre libro Le Dee e gli Dei dell’antica Europa, Marija Gimbutas presenta un ipotesi sulla religione dell’antica Europa. Durante il neolitico e l’età del rame ... dalla metà del V millennio a.C. fino alla metà del III millennio a.C., si delinea attraverso i reperti archeologici una cultura dai tratti unitari. (...) Secondo questa tesi l’antica Europa prima delle invasioni indoeuropee ha conosciuto, dalla fine del paleolitico fino al neolitico, una cultura che Gimbutas non definisce matriarcale, secondo la terminologia di Bachofen, bensi matrifocale. (...) Essa appare pacifica e sedentaria, in un territorio che si estende dal litorale orientale del Mar Nero e del Mediterraneo fini all’Egeo e l’Adriatico. In tutti i reperti archeologici della zona, che sono moltissimi, la Gimbutas rinviene statuine di una dea rappresentata come la corpulenta venere paleolitica. A volte ha le fattezze di un uccello acquatico, a volte come una donna serpente; queste figurine inoltre presentano spesso la particolarità di rappresentare sia una donna poderosa, dai glutei pronunciati, e sia la forma di un fallo. A questa dea spesso si accompagna qualche animale... Dopo che le invasioni indoeuropee ebbero imposto una cultura patriarcale violenta, di pastori seminomadi, il culto della dea sopravvisse probabilmente nell’antica Grecia e nell’Anatolia occidentale dove la dea ha ormai preso le 8 CULIANU IN ITALIA 93 forme delle possenti divinità Ecate e Artemide, poi imparentate con le dee anatoliche... (...) Talvolta dove c’è una grande madre da venerare, c’è anche un grande fallo, e l’accento può cadere su un’infinità di aspetti della sacralità che mai si escludono a vicenda. Non c’è un modello fisso tale per cui la grande madre escluda un dio maschile. A Mohenjo Daro e Harappa nella valle dell’Indo, verso il duemila a.C. fiori una civiltà il cui culto domestico era incentrato sulla matrona divina, mentre il culto pubblico prendeva di mira il fallo di un animale potente. Nello stesso modo in cui la terra senza aratro e senza seme non produce virgulti, così donna e uomo non sono contrari ma complementari, come le due facce di una moneta o di un foglio di carta. Nell’opera di Carmela Borgery, The God’s Obscured, l’autrice ha tracciato la metamorfosi delle dee in sante durante il medioevo cristiano. La sua tesi, che è stata poi abbracciata da vari rappresentanti della corrente femminista non radicale americana, evidenzia che c’è una continuità tra l’antica Europa e l’Europa medievale. Il cristianesimo è una religione chiaramente patrifocale eppure nel basso medioevo, come sappiamo, Maria ritorna con onore nella sacra famiglia celeste in qualità né più né meno di madre di dio e non di semplice generatrice di Cristo. (...) Il più possente ricettacolo cristiano dell’antica dea madre è la vergine Maria. Come la dea Demetra essa è capace di influire sulla produzione dei cereali e, se è ben disposta, il grano cresce subito nei campi, in caso contrario appassisce. (...) Ora compierò un passo pericoloso lanciandomi nel vuoto, perché ormai la grande dea dopo Giordano Bruno, dopo il ‘600, il Cinque-Seicento, non è più visibile... La sacralità femminile compie un passo, per così dire, miracoloso, scende in terra coinvolgendo la donna; coinvolgendola nel sacro più che nel passato. Ovviamente non voglio dire che non ci fossero prima molte categorie di sacerdotesse, profetesse, sciamane o streghe che partecipavano direttamente alla dimensione del sacro, né penso alla sacralità di funzioni tipicamente femminili come la gestazione, il parto e la nutrizione... penso qui invece ad un meccanismo, che poi cercherò di illustrare con l’aiuto di qualche diapositiva, molto complesso, e che per natura non sembrerebbe coinvolgere nessuna sacralità, invece ci conduce quanto mai vicino alla dimensione sacrale perché probabilmente può darci una spiegazione di come essa si formi e nasca. Mi spiego: le funzioni misteriose della donna, le sue possibilità di accogliere e generare una nuova vita sono state oggi desacralizzate..., uno dei risultati di questa liberazione è stato lo spostamento della sacralità che non mi sembra più così incentrata sui misteri della vita e della morte. E’interessante notare che da una parte, il culto della dea scende dalle sue altezze, dalle alture celesti e metafisiche e investe la donna medesima, e d’altra parte la donna non è più vista, e riporto qui un’espressione cara a Mircea Eliade, come “ierofania della Vita”, ma come un essere di cui o in cui si creano e si coltivano certe ambiguità, un monstrum, etimologicamente una creatura per essere mostrata. Questa è l’ipotesi che cercherò di illustrare, e cioè che la sacralità scende ora nel corpo femminile come se questo non fosse altro che una astrazione la cui 94 ROBERTA MORETTI 9 realtà è negoziabile. A riguardo mi vengono in mente quei lobbisti che portano dei bottoni con delle iscrizioni buffe, una delle quali dice: reality is negotiable (la realtà è negoziabile). Non esiste un concetto di realtà stabile, la realtà siamo noi a farla, la producono le nostre menti e in effetti, come si vedrà tra poco, non esiste un corpo di donna ma uno strumento la cui realtà è negoziabile, nel senso che lo si può cambiare e rendere visualmente diverso in sommo grado; da un’epoca all’altra lo si è fatto e in modi molto diversi. (...) Mi occuperò di un solo aspetto di questa transformazione, ed èquello dell’apparizione e continuazione della moda del tacco alto. (...) Il fenomeno del tacco alto è di solito associato, sia storicamente che tipologicamente, al trattamento cosmetico delle labbra e delle unghie femminili, ma io dovrò qui limitarmi soltanto ai tacchi. (...) Prima di cominciare vorrei aggiungere una cosa, e cioè che qui la sacralità non è palese, tutt’altro, essa è rinchiusa all’interno di mille gusci che non hanno apparentemente nulla di sacro. Se però leggiamo i segni come si deve, realizzeremo di quanto sia seria e profonda la dimensione del fenomeno e di quanto questa dimensione coinvolga le medesime facoltà che noi associamo con la venerazione e il culto delle divinità. Cominciamo con un po’ di storia, parlavo prima della donna come monstrum, una combinazione che si riscontra già nel mondo antico come quella che combina il corpo umano e quello equino. Questa combinazione ha una parte importantissima nella costituzione, accettazione e successo della moda dei tacchi alti; qui comincia la storia vera e propria, a partire dallo zoccolo. Gli zoccoli furono probabilmente introdotti a Venezia nel XV secolo. Il primo paio fu descritto nel 1494 da un viaggiatore sbalordito, un toscano che andava a Gerusalemme e fermatosi a Venezia vide e descrisse ciò che poi verrà ripetuto ad nauseam fino al XVII secolo: degli zoccoli che rendono il camminare problematico. Le cortigiane venete che avevano adottato questi zoccoli non potevano più camminare senza l’aiuto di due serve, e anche in questo caso a grande fatica. A questo punto ci sarebbero varie cose da dire: sebbene l’origine storica degli zoccoli sia orientale e la moda sia stata ripresa dagli Arabi, essa è stata incoraggiata sia localmente che in altre parti d’Italia dal clero. Il Vaticano ha incoraggiato nel ‘500 questa moda degli zoccoli perché metteva fine ai balli e nascondeva le parti inferiori del corpo femminile. A Venezia questa moda veniva incoraggiata sia da laici intorno al Doge che dal clero, per far sì che la donna non uscisse più tanto di casa. Il coturno greco ad esempio, simile ai sandali a piattaforma, serviva agli attori sul palcoscenico per impersonare divinità, in quanto le divinità dovevano essere più alte dei comuni mortali. Esisteva poi una leggenda greca secondo cui la moda degli zoccoli ricevesse, similmente al consiglio veneto, l’assenso e l’incoraggiamento dei sapienti per far sì che la donna rimanesse a casa il più possibile. Qui incontriamo tutti i fondamentalismi religiosi basati sull’idea che la donna debba essere una casalinga chiusa tra quattro mura. La più pazzesca conseguenza 10 CULIANU IN ITALIA 95 di questo principio si manifestò all’inizio dell’XI secolo quando il califfo fatimide del Cairo Al Hakim il pazzo, prese delle misure che proibivano a tutte le donne di uscire dalle loro case. Alle vedove che non avevano nessuno da mandare a comprare loro il vitto, il califfo faceva andare dei negozianti ambulanti, ai quali però non era consentito valicare la soglia di case né di vedere in viso la donna; per questo motivo disponevano di una specie di scopa mediante la quale consegnavano il vitto e si facevano pagare. A partire dal 1490 circa, la moda degli zoccoli si estese in tutta Europa. Nel’500 in Inghilterra alla corte Elisabettiana si portavano zoccoli estremanente alti, potevano arrivare ad un’altezza di più di un metro. La moda dei tacchi alti compare e scompare, si potrebbe ricostruirla in un ritmo sinusoidale (...) fino alla fine dell’800 primi del’900, quando si stabilizza e da allora non ci saranno più interruzioni. Dopo questa breve scorsa alla storia della moda degli zoccoli resta il quesito fondamentale del perché mai essa sia stata adottata, e a quale bisogno profondo risponda. Il corpo è flessibile, malleabile, la cultura prevale sulla natura transformando attraverso la moda, il corpo in qualcosa di strano. Se pensiamo ad esempio alla moda del corsetto, potremo forse farci un’idea di certe caricature dalla vita stretta. In tale situazione non era possibile neppure sedersi, ma la moda imponeva alla donna di portare il corsetto per mostrare la vita sottile. (...) Il mio intento è di mostrare come la moda possa transformare il corpo femminile in un monstrum, e alla base di tutto sta certamente un processo sacrale da individuare. Ed è proprio in questa trasformazione che, secondo me, si cela oggi una delle fonti maggiori della sacralità femminile, nel tipo di processo, seppure esso sia storicamente difficile da leggere e scoprire. Un tipo di processo che andrebbe inoltre collegato, come hanno mostrato vari antropologi, alle teorie odierne della ominizzazione. L’odierna antropologia mette in risalto le interazioni, il processo mimetico fra uomo e animali, specialmente predatori. In conclusione tale vicenda, secondo me affascinante, mette a nudo il processo di secolarizzazione della sacralità femminile”. NOTE 1. Elémire Zolla, Ioan Petru Culianu 1950–1991, Tallone, 1994, p. 11. 2. Paola Zambelli, L’ambigua natura della magia, Mondadori, Milano, 1991, p. 286. 3. Paul Oskar Kristeller, Il pensiero filosofico di Marsilio Ficino, Le Lettere, Firenze, 1988 (edizione riveduta). 4. Giovanni Casadio, Ricordo di Ioan Petru Culianu (1950–1991), in “Religioni e Società”, 16 Anno VIII, maggio-agosto 1993. 5. Intervista rilasciata alla scrivente dal Prof. L.E. Sullivan nell’aprile del 1997, quando fu invitato dalla Prof. ssa Grazia Marchianò ad Arezzo per una conferenza che si è tenuta in Facoltà il 23/1/1997 sul tema: Spazio e sacralità nelle culture umane. Frammenti primordiali. 6. Ricordo di Ioan Petru Culianu (1950–1991), in “Religioni e Società”, 16, maggio-agosto 1993. 7. “Abstracta”, Marzo 1989, n. 35. 8. Grazia Marchianò, Sugli orienti del pensiero. La natura illuminata e la sua estetica, vol. I, II Rubbettino, Mesina, 1994. 9. Gli interventi a questa presentazione furono poi pubblicati in E. Zolla, Tre discorsi metafisici 1989–1990, Guida, Napoli, 1991. 10. I cui Atti sono stati pubblicati in due volumi: The World’s Parliament of Religions. An Illustrated and Popular Story of the World’s First Parliament of Religions Held in Chicago, (Rev. J.H. Barrow a cura di), in coincidenza con l’esposizione colombiana del 1893, “Reviews of Reviews”, London, 1893. Nel 1993 si tiene a Chicago il 96 11. 12. 13. 14. ROBERTA MORETTI Parliament of the World’s Religions. Declaration toward a Global Ethic, gli atti vengono pubblicati prima in tedesco nel 1995 poi in inglese con il titolo: Yes to a Global Ethic, (Hans Kung, a cura di), SCM Press, London, 1996. Ioan P. Couliano, Alcune riflessioni sulla magia e la sua fine, in La religione della terra, Grazia Marchianò (a cura di), Red, Como, 1991. Ricordo di Ioan Petru Culianu (1950–1991), in “Religioni e Società” 16, maggio-agosto 1993. Ivi. Vedi ad esempio Jurgis Baltrusaitis, Il medioevo fantastico. Antichità ed esotismi nell’arte gotica, 11 Milano, Adelphi, 1973. (Il edizione 1993). Ed anche Francesco Zambon (a cura di), Il fisiologo, Milano, Adelphi, 1975 (3° ed. 1990). 15. Questo enunciato richiama un principio della fisica: il “principio cosmologico antropico”, vedi John D. Barrow e Frank J. Tipler, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, Oxford University Press, 1998. Secondo questo ragionamento l’universo in cui ci troviamo presenta determinate caratteristiche posto che l’uomo o altro essere senziente, sia li presente a osservarlo (n.d.r.). L’INSEGNAMENTO DEL ROMENO IN ITALIA FRA LE DUE GUERRE MONDIALI CARMEN BURCEA Chiarimento Premesse – Propositi – Fonti Nel prendere in esame l’argomento del presente saggio, abbiamo individuato alcuni punti di partenza: un articolo dell’Egregio Professor G. Lãzãrescu in occasione del centenario dalla fondazione del primo lettorato di lingua romena in Italia1; la conferenza del docente T. Onciulescu sugli “Inizi e sviluppo dell’insegnamento del romeno in Italia”2; lo studio firmato da M. Ruffini3, panoramico ma privo di documenti d’archivio o di legami di tipo politicodiplomatico, che attualmente si rivelano impegnativi ecc. La nostra indagine, orientata a valorizzare e a collocare nel giusto periodo storico i suddetti documenti, è parte di un progetto di studio di ampio respiro sulla diplomazia culturale italo-romena fra le due guerre, in seno alla quale il tema dell’insegnamento reciproco delle due lingue costituisce un capitolo per nulla trascurabile. Focalizziamo l’attenzione sul periodo interbellico, che segna la fase più intensa dei rapporti italo-romeni; fase indubbiamente dominata dalle tematiche culturali4. Proprio questi anni vedono sorgere (o risorgere) i lettorati di lingua romena nella penisola italica. Va detto però che il nostro saggio non si avvale di fonti italiane, esistenti probabilmente negli archivi delle varie università (salvo quello dell’Ateneo patavino), ma fa riferimento agli archivi del Ministero della Propaganda Nazionale (Mpn), della Cultura Nazionale e dei Culti (Mcnc), dell’Istruzione Pubblica (Mip) ecc. conservati nell’Archivio Nazionale Storico Centrale di Bucarest (ANSC). Si è dimostrato utile anche il Fondo Italia, custodito nell’Archivio del Ministero degli Affari Esteri (AMAE). Talvolta, abbiamo arricchito le notizie qui individuate con fonti italiane, recuperate nella Direzione Generale per la Propaganda (Dgp) dall’Archivio Centrale dello Stato Italiano (ACS) oppure da quello Scuole (AS) e Affari Politici (AP) dell’Archivio Storico del Ministero degli Affari Esteri (ASMAE). Certamente, non ci sarebbe stato possibile prescindere dai carteggi dei maestri di lingua romena riferiti al periodo in esame. Quelle pagine, malgrado la lenta e irreparabile corrosione del tempo, conservano ancora i riverberi del loro passato. Abbiamo perciò intrapreso un percorso di documentazione anche nella Biblioteca dell’Accademia Romena (BAR), Servizio Manoscritti. Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 97–106, Bucharest, 2005. 98 CARMEN BURCEA Lettorati – Centri di cultura Significato dei Lettorati – Genesi – Regolamenti Criteri di selezione – Compensi Ruolo dei lettori – Pilastri 2 Dagli echi risorgimentali all’effervescente periodo interbellico, dai depositari di questa tradizione fino ai rappresentanti dei giorni nostri, i lettorati di lingua e civiltà hanno costituito forse il mezzo più efficace della propaganda culturale romena in Italia. L’analisi della propaganda romena svolta in Italia ci ha agevolato l’approccio ad un tale argomento5. La Legazione romena di Roma ed i vari consolati, gli addetti stampa e i consiglieri culturali, i professori e gli studenti, sono stati coinvolti tutti quanti in questa rete di trasmissione/emissione di informazioni concepita dal Centro. Per quanto fossero tutti dotati di competenza professionale, alcuni dei nostri rappresentati all’estero vennero morsi dall’invidia, dalla superbia, dall’avidità e, sfortunatamente, si lasciarono corrodere dai loro vezzi. Di conseguenza, scivolarono in secondo piano gli aspetti davvero rilevanti della nostra propaganda. Così, accadde che i docenti di lingua romena ricoprirono con frequenza quel ruolo al loro posto, diventando un punto di riferimento. Le relazioni su ogni lettorato avviato in Italia sono molto diverse tra loro. Il fatto è dovuto soprattutto all’intervallo storico in cui i lettorati sono stati attivi e, poi, in misura minore, ai lettori stessi. Alcuni lettori ci presentano resoconti formali, mentre altri si spendono in ricche descrizioni. Alcuni si limitano alla cattedra, laddove altri si fanno coinvolgere anima e corpo nella loro professione. Per alcuni gli strumenti specifici del lavoro sono sufficienti, mentre per altri i metodi per attrarre sempre più studenti sono inesauribili e spesso inediti: musica, folclore, storia, politica contemporanea — tutte queste ingegnosità didattiche sono documentate. R. Ortiz per esempio, chiedeva all’Ufficio Stampa delle riproduzioni dei discorsi dei più noti politici, affinché i suoi studenti acquisissero dimestichezza con la pronuncia della lingua romena. Cl. Isopescu, invece, era dell’idea che gli studenti italiani dovessero arrivare amarci in modo “non mediato” e perciò si impegnava per ottenere delle borse di studio affinché potessero usufruire di soggiorni di studio in Romania, a Vãlenii de Munte. M. Ruffini, nello stesso tempo, organizzava delle serate di musica tradizionale romena al giradischi. Tra i docenti di lingua romena in Italia c’è stato un vero e proprio spirito di emulazione. In genere, si sono reciprocamente apprezzati e hanno collaborato fra loro, condividendo affanni e successi. Comune denominatore tra tutti è il rapporto splendido che hanno sviluppato con lo storico letterario I.E. Torouþiu (1888–1953), il quale conosceva le loro richieste — donazioni di libri per le biblioteche romene, la pubblicazione di qualche studio loro oppure dei loro discenti ecc — meglio di chiunque altro. Non a caso, I.E. Torouþiu aveva alle spalle un’esperienza come assistente universitario di lingua romena all’Università di Francoforte, prima della Grande Guerra (1911–1913). Anche i glottologi italiani (G. Bretoni, M. Batoli, C. Tagliavini, A. Schiaffini, C. Merlo, 3 L’INSEGNAMENTO DEL ROMENO IN ITALIA 99 A. Monteverdi, C. Battisti, G. Devoto, B. Migliorini, A. Parducci, E. Levi, G. Serra etc.) gli hanno dato il loro appoggio. I docenti o i propagandisti ungheresi inseriti in altre strutture, al contrario, lo hanno guardato come un loro rivale, un perpetuo termine di paragone6. Il rapporto con le autorità romene sul suolo italico (la Legazione ed i consolati) comunque non fu dei migliori. Di debolezze, tensioni, incomunicabilità e buone intenzioni mai realizzate ce ne furono molte. Dal Centro proveniva l’ossessivo richiamo alle “ragioni del budget” stanziato per la propaganda all’estero. Questo disagio fu peraltro controbilanciato dallo zelo dei docenti. E’ proprio loro che dobbiamo ringraziare se furono frequenti le notizie riguardanti i romeni nella stampa italiana dell’epoca e se oggi, di conseguenza, possiamo disporre di una così ricca bibliografia. Grazie a loro, abbiamo accesso a un patrimonio dal quale partire per la “riconquista” il presente. I lettorati di lingua romena hanno avuto efficacia come indicatori dell’espansione della cultura romena all’estero, agendo al contempo come basi di lavoro sul terreno della diplomazia romena. A mano a mano, essi diventano strumento di mediazione e consueta modalità operativa della nostra politica culturale. In queste due queste caratteristiche risiede il loro valore. Per ciò che riguarda la loro genesi, annotiamo una distinzione tra i lettorati storici, di eco risorgimentale (a Torino — G.V. Ruscalla; a Venezia — M.A. Canini), e quelli sorti nel periodo fra le due guerre — punto di partenza per la situazione che oggi ereditiamo7. La loro comparsa non è caotica né casuale, anche se le apparenze potrebbero facilmente condurre ad una tale conclusione. L’istituzione dei lettorati non é dovuta tanto all’entusiasmo o all’idoneità di uno o più professori o ad altri fattori individuali, quanto alla compartecipazione e al pieno coinvolgimento dello Stato nel sostenere l’iniziativa con mezzi propri. L’insegnamento del romeno all’estero era infatti connesso alla propaganda. La creazione dei lettorati era funzionale alle esigenze della propaganda romena all’estero. Di conseguenza, i più importanti saranno costituiti in Germania, seguita da vicino dall’ Italia e poi dalla Francia. Il loro ordinamento era regolato dalle convenzioni culturali concluse con i vari paesi, sulla base del principio della reciprocità8. In Italia, le cattedre di lingua romena hanno vissuto più che altro due momenti di espansione ragguardevoli dal punto di vista politico: nel periodo del governo N. Iorga (1931/2), quando si svolgono delle trattative in questa direzione-anche se i risultati tardarono di qualche anno- e nella congiuntura venutasi a creare con l’Accordo culturale italo-romeno, firmato l’8 aprile 1943, dopo una gestazione assai lunga. I lettorati preesistenti saranno obbligati a rispettare le nuove normative. La questione della paternità dei lettorati non è tuttora risolta. Claudio Isopescu si aggiudica il merito di aver creato i lettorati di Milano e Torino, Firenze e Napoli, e ancora di quello sorto a Padova. Indubbiamente, Isopescu fu un fervido sostenitore di questi e si mosse verso il suo obiettivo attraverso l’Associazione Italo-Romena di Roma, anche se siamo del parere che gli mancasse il potere effettivo per essere il vero fondatore. Tanto più che le formule tipo “sono troppo piccolo e la mia voce risuona nel deserto” sono ricorrenti nei suoi carteggi. 100 CARMEN BURCEA 4 Il lettorato di Milano debutta sotto gli auspici del Consolato Romeno. Il fatto è confermato proprio da Gino Lupi: “Dalla mia iniziativa e con l’appoggio del console A. Ricci e del Sig. Monti, segretario della Camera di Commercio, ho aperto nel 1931 il mio corso di romeno all’Università Reale di Milano”9. Il professore italiano era sostenuto in questa sua impresa anche da Aron Cotruº, sotto il consiglio del quale tradusse, proprio in quell’anno, il dramma “San Francisco” di Nicola Iorga. Da Torino M. Ruffini affermava esplicitamente di essere stato incaricato da N. Iorga10. A Firenze, le cose erano state stabilite durante il ricevimento dello stesso N. Iorga nel febbraio 1935, come indica anche il professor Carlo Battisti (1882–1977) della Scuola di Glottologia11. A Napoli, la questione della fondazione di una cattedra di lingua romena aveva trovato un sostenitore nella persona del professor Ezio Levi (1884–1944), titolare della cattedra di filologia romanza. Per ciò che riguarda il lettorato di Padova, il merito va esclusivamente all’azione svolta da Ramiro Ortiz. Nonostante cio, nel 1937, Isopescu scriveva a Liviu Rebreanu (1885–1944), presidente della Società degli Scrittori Romeni e direttore del Teatro Nazionale di Bucarest: “Il mio travaglio è diventato ancor più grande: ho fondato dei corsi di romeno a Turin, a Milano, a Firenze e a Napoli. Quei posti sono occupati da miei ex allievi e loro non fanno niente senza domandarmi.”12 Nello stesso anno 1937, a Camil Petrescu (1894–1957), all’epoca redattore alla “Revista Fundaþiilor Regale”, scriveva: “Forse avrai saputo che sono riuscito a fondare una conferenza di romeno a Turin e un lettorato alle università di Firenze e Napoli”.13 Nel 1938 scriveva a Cezar Petrescu (1892–1961), all’epoca segretario generale nel Ministero delle Arti e direttore del giornale “Romania”: “Sono riuscito su iniziativa propria di creare, io, un uomo semplice, il primo insegnamento di romeno a Roma e in 10 anni di fondare sempre io i lettorati di Napoli, Firenze, Padova, Milano e Turin. A Padova, Ortiz è professore di letteratura romanica e la signorina Nina Façon (richiesta da Ortiz) è lettrice di lingua romena.”14 Se da parte dello storico N. Iorga15 i documenti non abbondano (ci pervengono implicitamente), per l’anno 1942 c’é un documento che contiene tutto ciò che potrebbe interessarci. Si tratta del decreto No. 58.108 / 16 marzo 1942, emanato dal Ministero della Cultura Nazionale; in pratica la normativa dei lettorati di lingua romena presso le Università straniere16. Quali erano i criteri di selezione dei lettori? Per quanto riguarda la loro specializzazione, si specificava che non dovevano essere soltanto dei linguisti, ma anche storici, etnografi e giuristi (l’area di studi umanistici). Tra le condizioni di reclutamento, esposte nel decreto, ma anticipate dal progetto di regolamento17, si nota la competenza scientifica, la conoscenza della lingua, la cultura generale ecc. Si appezzavano come tratti essenziali del loro profilo “la possibilità d’azione, lo spirito d’iniziativa, le qualità sociali per rappresentare il paese”. La stragrande maggioranza dei lettori romeni (Claudiu Isopescu, Gheorghe Caragaþã, Teodor Onciulescu, Petre Ciureanu, Petru Iroaie, Marina Vlasiu Lupaº) vennero in qualità d’ex soci della Scuola Romena di Roma. L’impiego da parte 5 L’INSEGNAMENTO DEL ROMENO IN ITALIA 101 dello stato romeno di coloro che aveva aiutato a perfezionarsi in Italia (creando il quadro giuridico e consegnando il sostegno materiale) si dimostrava veramente proficuo per ambo le parti. L’investimento dello stato romeno si dimostra, quantomeno in questo caso, a lungo termine. Una circolare del febbraio 1944 rendeva nota la disposizione del ministro della Propaganda Nazionale Al. Marcu, il quale valutava inopportuno attribuire il titolo alle donne, portando come motivazione l’alto valore strategico delle cattedre per la nostra propaganda all’estero18. L’unica bocciata fu Iolanda Eminescu, laureata in Legge, aspirante all’incarico di lettore nell’Istituto Romeno di Madrid. In Italia però non si verificarono casi di questo tipo. Sempre nel decreto No. 58.108/942 si specificava che potevano esser accreditati, col titolo di “lettore d’onore” e sulla base di un contratto, anche quei cittadini di nazionalità diversa che avessero dimostrato di svolgere un’attività leale ed incessante a beneficio della Romania. In conformità con l’articolo 80 della Legge sull’organizzazione dell’insegnamento superiore del 23 maggio 1942, il contratto si faceva sulla base di un resoconto motivato del professore, precedentemente sottoposto al dibattito e al voto del consiglio. I “lettori d’onore” erano stipendiati dal budget del Ministero della Cultura. La Facoltà di Lettere di Bucarest centralizzava il processo di selezione dei candidati. Qui si presentavano le candidature e si organizzava il concorso. I lettori erano incaricati dal Ministero della Cultura con il consenso della Propaganda Nazionale per un anno e con diritto d’essere riconfermati ogni due anni, in base alle raccomandazioni inoltrate dalle istituzioni culturali romene esistenti in quel paese. Dopo l’investitura, ogni lettore riceveva la conferma dall’Università presso la quale era delegato. Sin dal 1941 si era auspicato un criterio standard per stabilire lo stipendio dei lettori, ma ciò non avvenne. Le grosse differenze di retribuzione creavano sempre delle “rivalità inutili” tra i lettori, senza considerare il fatto che gli stipendi non venivano pagati regolarmente. Le retribuzioni dei lettori erano a carico dello Stato, solo che alcuni venivano pagati da Ministero della Propaganda Nazionale e altri da quello della Cultura Nazionale. Il ruolo dei lettori non si limitava però a quello cattedratico. Loro erano i rappresentanti culturali dello Stato romeno e si trasformavano in portavoce del punto di vista nazionale nelle questioni tanto dibattute in quel periodo, che riguardavano principalmente i dissidi tra i romeni ed i magiari, spesso manifestati nello spazio italiano. Si specificava proprio che: ”La loro condizione didattica era soltanto il biglietto da visita. In realtà la missione era più complessa e delicata. Questa richiedeva, al di là dell’addestramento intellettuale, una grande abilità e solo essa poteva legittimare la loro presenza nel paese in cui si trovavano.”19 In conformità col articolo 13, i lettori avevano l’obbligo di compilare relazioni mensili sulle attività, d’informare i due ministeri ed il dirigente dell’ufficio 102 CARMEN BURCEA 6 diplomatico dall’Italia sull’andamento della loro attività accademica. Le comunicazioni non erano dirette. La Scuola Romena di Roma faceva da tramite. Non sempre le cose avvenivano in questo modo. Scarlat Lambrino lamentava l’ingerenza della nostra Legazione: “Imbarazzato, P. Ciureanu mi ha confessato che non lo possono fare, perché hanno ricevuto ordine formale da parte della Legazione Romena a Roma di non indirizzare i loro rapporti che alla Legazione.”20 Grazie a queste relazioni siamo in grado adesso di ricostituire le tematiche, i manuali, gli orari delle lezioni, i nominativi degli studenti, gli argomenti delle loro tesi di laurea, le manifestazioni culturali ecc. Quali erano le fondamenta di questa costruzione? Una volta costituiti, i lettorati venivano appoggiati dall’Accademia di Romania a Roma21 e dall’Associazione culturale italo-romena22, capeggiata dall’accademico Giulio Bertoni23, assecondato dal professor Claudio Isopescu. Dalla Romania invece, come già detto, i Ministeri della Cultura e della Propaganda Nazionale gestivano, controllavano, agevolavano l’attività dei lettorati. I manuali più utilizzati del periodo furono la Grammatica24 e l’Antologia25 di C. Tagliavini, il Compendio di N. Cartojan26, il Manualetto27 di R. Ortiz, il dizionario28 di Al. Marcu, l’Antologia di M. Ruffini29. Tuttavia, dalle materie di insegnamento di questi anni spesso scaturiscono le tracce dei libri che saranno pubblicati negli anni successivi dai lettori stessi, a volte per crearsi nuovi strumenti di lavoro, altre volte per venire incontro agli interessi mostrati dagli studenti. Accanto ai lavori dei maestri appariranno anche alcune tesi di laurea dei discepoli30. Durante la guerra, lo sbarco delle truppe alleate nel sud dell’Italia, dei bombardamenti, del crollo del fascismo, i docenti di lingua romena si confrontarono con i problemi della società italiana: prezzi massimali, mercato nero, il sistema delle cartelle alimentarie (150 gr. pane/giorno, 1 uova/settimana, 150 gr. carne/ settimana). Per un periodo le università e le scuole rimasero chiuse. In queste condizioni avranno scandito pure loro, come gli italiani, “Pace e Pane!”. I trattati di pace, a guerra conclusa, contenevano i germi “della guerra fredda”, che consacra la divisione del Europa in due blocchi (Est-Ovest) inconciliabili dal punto di vista ideologico. In questo contesto, i lettori romeni saranno richiamati in patria. La maggioranza rifiuta di eseguire l’ordine. Specialmente dopo il richiamo dei direttori dell’Accademia di Romania a Roma (1 aprile 1947), i lettorati cessarono di rappresentare una costruzione romena. Un primo passo era stato già fatto nel 1946 con la soppressione d’alcuni lettorati (il posto di assistente a Roma, i lettorati di Napoli, Genova, Venezia, Bari)31. Non meno priva d’asperità fu l’evoluzione postbellica dei lettorati rappresentati da docenti italiani. Il cambiamento del regime politico determinò inchieste ed epurazioni. La Commissione d’inchiesta del Ministero Italiano dell’Istruzione Pubblica analizzò i casi di M. Ruffini e G. Lupi, “esonerati alla fine da qualsiasi colpa”32. 7 L’INSEGNAMENTO DEL ROMENO IN ITALIA 103 A fatica alcuni lettori riusciranno a mantenere i loro posti universitari e saranno attivi nell’ ambito dell’alta cultura italiana distinguendosi nei decenni successivi come l’elite romena in esilio33. Rappresetanti Dove ci sono stati e chi sono quelli che hanno raffigurato i lettorati di lingua romena in Italia? Claudiu Isopescu34 (1894–1956) insegnò per primo la lingua romena all’Università di Roma (1926). Nel 1929 divenne conferenziere e dal 1936 fu titolare di cattedra fino alla sua scomparsa35. Per un periodo il suo ruolo di docente venne ampliato con gli incarichi ufficiali conferiti dallo stato romeno — come addetto di stampa oppure culturale, sempre a Roma. A Torino, dopo Giovenale Vegezzi Ruscalla36 (1799–1885) — reputato il più illustre filoromeno dell’epoca, che inaugurò il 15 dicembre del 1863 il primo corso libero di Lingua e Letteratura Romena37 durato fino nel 1879 — e dopo Romeo Lovera38 all’ Istituto Superiore di Studi commerciali di Torino fu Mario Ruffini a rappresentare l’insegnamento del romeno tra il 1931 e il 1967. Il primo ad insegnare la lingua romena a Milano fu Romeo Lovera39, del quale magistero non ne abbiamo purtroppo sufficienti notizie. Proseguirono sulla sua strada Gino Lupi, dal 1931 all’Università Statale, e dal 1943 Marcello Camillucci40, al quale venne affidato il lettorato romeno presso l’Università Cattolica Sacro Cuore di Milano41. La fondazione del lettorato romeno a Padova42 segna una nuova tappa nella vita di Ramiro Ortiz43. Nel 1937 fu creato un lettorato di lingua romena, rappresentato inizialmente da Nina Façon (1 ottobre 1937–1 febbraio 1939). Revocata, a causa della situazione generata dalle leggi razziali, la Façon sarà sostituita da Alexandrina Mititelu44. Nel 1936, con l’iscritto No. 73 851/1936, Gheorghe Caragaþã (1907–1978)45, venne nominato lettore di lingua romena a Firenze, dove si dedicò a questo apostolato per ben quarant’anni. Teodor Onciulescu46, investito lettore di lingua romena a Napoli a partire il 1937, insegnò per quasi 30 anni nella Facoltà di Lettere e all’Istituto Universitario Orientale. A Bologna, dopo il 1943, si avviò un lettorato di lingua romena raffigurato da Nicolae Moldovan e poi da Constantin Vicol. Petre Ciureanu47 fu incaricato come lettore di lingua romena nel 1942 presso la Facoltà di Economia e Commercio di Genova e dopo la guerra vi insegnò il francese. A Palermo Petru Iroaie (1907–1984), debuttò come lettore di romeno alla fine del 1942 ed insegnò fino alla sua scomparsa. Marina Vlasiu Lupaº48 inviata all’Università di Bari nel febbraio 1943, rinunciò all’incarico dopo soltanto un anno49 essendo assunta dal Istituto Sud-Est Europeo 104 CARMEN BURCEA 8 di Bucarest. A sostituirla saranno Nina Façon (1909–1974) e, successivamente, Demetrio Marin. Depositari della tradizione Rappresentanti d’oggi Prospettive adeguate ai presenti traguardi Quali sono i depositari di questa tradizione? Dopo la generazione rappresentata da Al. Niculescu a Udine, Silvio Guarnieri a Genova, George Lãzãrescu e Manlio Coppeti a Pisa, Ovidiu Drâmba a Torino, Rosa del Conte e Emil Turdeanu a Roma, Pasquale Buonincontro a Napoli, ne é sorta un’altra. Quali i docenti di lingua romena dell’Italia odierna? Marco Cugno* a Torino, Teresa Ferro50 a Udine, Roberto Scagno a Padova, Bruno Mazzoni a Pisa, Luisa Valmarin e Gheorghe Carageani a Roma, tutti quanti a confermare una continuità. Lo stato romeno ha sancito la loro benemerenza51 e dimostra una tendenza alla crescita del numero dei lettorati romeni all’estero appoggiati dall’ Istituto di Lingua Romena52 e dall’ Istituto Culturale Romeno53. La lingua romena, anche se preceduta da altri idiomi più internazionali (inglese, francese, tedesco, spagnolo)54, non cessa di interessare gli studenti italiani, facendo germogliare tra loro i futuri filo-romeni55. Concludiamo il nostro studio con la convinzione che i lettorati romeni all’estero, ovunque essi siano collocati, potrebbero significare tuttora non solo un mezzo di diffusione della lingua romena in veste accademica, ma anche un’opportunità di rappresentanza, un centro di propaganda di grande responsabilità per l’immagine che proiettano, un luogo di alta produzione culturale e di informazione sulla Romania e sui rapporti bilaterali, nonché un sostegno essenziale allo sforzo di integrazione in Europa. Chiaramente, l’eco delle sue manifestazioni non potrebbe mai essere quello vagheggiato, in assenza dell’apporto e della totale corrispondenza con le istituzioni culturali e diplomatiche esistenti nei vari paesi. Prendiamo allora esempio dal passato. NOTE 1. Gheorghe Lãzãrescu, Giovenale Vegezzi Ruscalla, primul profesor de limba românã în Italia, Estratto da Analele Universitãþii Bucureºti, Secþia ªtiinþe Sociale – Filologie No. 28, Anno XII, 1963, Bucarest, 8 p. 2. O manifestaþie a secþiei din Italia a Societãþii Academice Române, in: “Revista Scriitorilor Români”, no. 2, 1963, p. 189. 3. Mario Ruffini, L’insegnamento del rumeno in Italia, “Il Veltro”, XIII, 1969, No. 1–2, pp. 305–312. 4. Pasquale Buonincontro, La presenza della Romania in Italia nel secolo XX. Contributo bibliografico 1900–1980, Napoli, De Simone Editore, p. 14. 5. Vedi Carmen Burcea, Propaganda româneascã în Italia în perioada interbelicã, in: “Revista de ªtiinþe Politice ºi Relaþii Internaþionale”, no. 1/2005, pp. 94–108. 6. La prima cattedra universitaria di Lingua e letteratura magiara fu fondata nel 1927 a Roma, i titolari essendo i direttori dell’Accademia d’Ungheria (Tibor Gerevich, Gyula Miskolczy, Eugenio Koltay Kaster). Ulteriormente, l’insegnamento di lingua magiara fu esteso alle * Preside dell’Associazione Italiana di Romenistica. L’INSEGNAMENTO DEL ROMENO IN ITALIA 9 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. università di Milano, Padova, Bologna, Napoli e Bari. Cf. Péter Sarközy, La “fortuna” della letteratura ungherese in Italia e di quella italiana in Ungheria, in: Italia e Ungheria. Storia, politica, società, letteratura, fonti, a cura di Francesco Guida e Rita Tolomeo, Atti dell’incontro di studio tenuto a Roma il 9–11novembre 1989, Edizioni Periferia, 1991, p. 237. M.O., parte I, No. 790/30.X. 2002. Programma di collaborazione culturale italo-romena per gli anni 2002–2005. Il problema dell’insegnamento italiano in Romania è assai complesso. Ci limitiamo ora a ricordare soltanto le cattedre più importanti: Ramiro Ortiz, Umberto Ciancialò, Bruno Manzone (Bucarest), Giandomenico Serra (Cluj), Silvio Guarnirei (Timiºoara), Mariano Baffi (Braºov), Paolo Soldati (Craiova), Giuseppe Petronio, Liberale Netto (Iaºi), Leonardo Salemi (Chiºinãu), Edgardo Giorgi-Alberti (Cernãuþi) Cf. ASMAE, Archivio Scuole (1936–1945), Romania, Pacco 109. Limba ºi Literatura românã în Italia. Bibliografia d-lui Gino Lupi, in: “Viaþa”, 31 dicembre 1941. A.N.S.C., Mip, Dossier 530/1932, f. 36. M. Ruffini a Gh. Gh. Mironescu, Ministro di Finanze, 13 settembre 1932. A.N.S.C., Mcnc, Dossier 2500/1943, Carlo Battisti al ministro dell’Istruzione Pubblica, 10 febbraio 1936. B.A.R., Corisp., S 45 (47)/CMLXIV, Cl. Isopescu a Liviu Rebreanu, 30 noiembrie 1937. Scrisori cãtre Camil Petrescu, vol. I, Ediþie îngrijitã, prefaþa, note ºi indici de Florica Ichim, Bucureºti, Editura Minerva, 1981, p. 42. Cl. Isopescu a Camil Petrescu, 6 aprile 1937. B.A.R., Corisp., S 40 (35)/ DCCXCVIIII, Cl. Isopescu a Cezar Petrescu, 9 augosto 1938. “L’Italia”, a. XX, No. 300, 18 dicembre 1931, Milano: “L’inizio di corsi romeni nelle università italiane corrisponde all’interessamento dei romeni per i corsi d’italiano introdotti nelle università di Bucarest, Cernautzi e Cluj per opera di S.E. professor Nicola Iorga”. Vedi anche Gino LUPI, Un romeno studioso dell’Italia: Nicola Iorga, “Rassegna Italo-Romena”, a. XIX, nov. 1940, pp. 4–5. Nell’incidenza del nuovo regolamento entravano anche i lettorati rappresentati da Emil Turdeanu a Sofia e poi Parigi; Eugen Tãnase – Montpellier; Constantin Velichi – Sofia; Ionel Grigoriu – Heidelberg; Al. Ciorãnescu – Sorbone e Grenoble; Octavian Vuia – Francoforte; Ion Popinceanu – Leipzig; Al. Dima – Viene; Victor Buescu – Lisabona; Al. Busuioceanu — Madrid ecc. A.N.S.C., Mpn, Informazioni, Dossier 813, f. 106–109. A.N.S.C., Mcnc, Insegnamento Superiore, Dossier 1560/1944, f. 48. 105 19. A.N.S.C., Mpn, Studi e Documenti, Dossier 167, f. 18. 20. A.N.S.C., Mcnc, Insegnamento Superiore, Dossier 2638/1943, f. 32. 21. A.N.S.C., MAE, Protocol, Dossier 14: legge No. 55/20 marzo 1944 [Riguardante la fondazione delle Scuole romene e gli Istituti culturali all’estero, le Borse di Stato] riconferma e completa la Legge no. 440 del 1941 per l’organizzazione delle Scuole Romene di Roma e Parigi. L’Articolo 32 precisa: “I Direttori delle Scuole Romene all’estero guidano e coordinano l’attività dei lettori di lingua romena all’estero. Laddove non ci sono tali scuole o istituti l’attività dei lettori sarà controllata dal capo missione.” 22. A.N.S.C., Mpn, Propaganda, Dossier 906. Fondata nel dicembre del 1931, codesta si auspicava di contribuire alla divulgazione della Romania in Italia attraverso serate culturali, conferenze, audizioni di musica romena. 23. ªtefan Cuciureanu, Un prieten al Românismului: Giulio Bertoni, in: “Convorbiri Literare”, LXXV/1942, no. 7–8, pp. 385–401; Th. Capidan, Giulio Bertoni, in: “Revista Fundaþiilor Regale”, 9, no. 8, 1942, pp. 436–437; Umberto Cianciolò, Giulio Bertoni ºi filosofia romanicã, Cartea Româneascã din Cluj, 1944, p. 28. 24. C. Tagliavini, Grammatica della lingua rumena, Bologna 1923, XX, p. 410. 25. Idem, Antologia rumena, Passi scelti ed annotati di autori rumeni, Heidelberg, G. Gross, 1923, p. 320. 26. N. Cartojan, Breve storia della letteratura romena, Roma, 1926 [Estratto da “L’Europa Orientale”, VI, p. 379–404]. 27. R. Ortiz, Manualetto rumeno, Bucarest, Bucovina, 1936, pp. 240+XXXIV. 28. Al. Marcu, Dicþionar roman-italian, Bucarest, 1929–1933, p. 337; a II-a edizione, Bucarest, Editura Alcalay, 1938, 624 pp.; a III-a, Bucarest, Atelierele Grafice Socec, 1941, p. 624; a IV-a, 1943, Bucarest, Atelierele Grafice Socec, p. 624. 29. M. Ruffini, Antologia Romena. Testi moderni, Modena, Soc. Tip. Modena, 1940, p. 164. 30. [Recensioni] M. Camillucci, L. Santangelo, Giorgio Coºbuc nella vita nelle opere, Roma, 1934; A. Colombo, Vita e opere di Ion Luca Caragiale, Roma, 1934, in: “Europa Orientale”, XVIII/1938, pp. 435–438; G. Lupi, W. Roccato, I. Al. Brãtescu – Voineºti novelliere, Roma, Signorelli, 1939; Lena Maria Bevilacqua, E. Gârleanu nella vitae nelle opere, Roma, Signorelli, 1939, in: “Europa Orientale”, XX/1940, pp. 147–151. F[ortunescu] C.D, Trei teze de doctorat italieneºti. Note, in: “Arhivele Olteniei”, XIV, nr. 79–82, maggio–dicembre 1935, p. 478–482. 31. A.N.S.C., M., Ed. Naz., Insegnamento Superiore, Dossier 680/1946, f. 29–30. Rapporto del 12 febbraio 1946 al ministro ªtefan Voitec. 32. Ibidem, f.111. Rapporto di Scarlat Lambrino a ªtefan Voitec, 24 settembre 1946. 106 CARMEN BURCEA 33. Vedi Florin Manolescu, Enciclopedia exilului literar românesc.1945–1989, Bucarest, Editura Compania, 2003. 34. George Lãzãrescu, Prezenþe româneºti în Italia, Bucarest, Editura Didacticã ºi Pedagogicã, 1995, pp. 122–148; Luigi Tonelli, Claudio Isopescu, Rassegna Nazionale, LIII, 1931, S. III, vol. XIV, pp. 105–109; T. ªoimaru, Cultura româneascã în Italia. Un pionier: prof. Claudiu Isopescu, in: “România Literarã”, I, 1939, nr. 20, p. 22. 35. Dal 1943, Franco Cardinalli, il figlio del Decano della Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia dell’Università di Roma, diventa suo assistente. Suo successore diretto alla cattedra dell’Università di Roma, fu Mariano Baffi. 36. Vedi Teodor D. Onciulescu, Contributo alla storia della filologia romanza in Italia. Giovenale Vegezzi-Ruscalla, Napoli, 1937. 37. G.V. Ruscalla, Prolusione al libero corso di lingua, letteratura e storia rumana nell’Università di Torino, detta il 15 dicembre 1863, Torino, Derossi e Dusso, 1863, 20 pp. 38. Vedi Note Italo-Romene. Per la cultura romena in Italia, in: “Romania. Rassegna degli interessi italo-romeni”, (II, 5), rivista diretta da M. Silvestri (1920–1922). Romeo Lovera, L’insegnamento della lingua romena nel R. Istituto Superiore di studi commerciali di Torino, Casale Monferrato, 1921. 39. Romeo Lovera, Grammatica e vocabolario della lingua rumena, Milano, Hoepli, 1892, pp. IV – 200; ed. a II-a 1906, p. 183; ed. a III-a 1917, p. 211; ed. IV-a 1933; ristamp. Milano, CisalpinoGoliardica, 1976, pp. VIII+213. 40. Marcello Camillucci si era addottorato con la tesi su La vita e l’opera di Panait Cerna, pubblicata a Roma [Istituto Europa Orientale, 1935, 169 pp.] per la quale aveva ricevuto, sempre tramite Isopescu, una sovvenzione di 500 Lire. Cf. A.N.S.C., Mpn, Propaganda, Dossier 957, f. 1. 41. A.N.S.C., Mcnc, Insegnamento Superiore, Dossier 2500/1943, f. 44. 42. A.N.S.C., Mpn, Propaganda, Dossier 1108/1933 –1943, f. 70. 43. Rimandiamo a Carmen Burcea, Ramiro Ortiz, Bucarest, Editura Noua Alternativã, 2004, p. 144. 10 44. Vedi Alexandrina Mititelo, Grammatica romena, Padova, Cedam, 1947, XII+248 pp.; Letteratura romena antica. Cenni storici – Breve antologia – Glossario, Padova, Liviana Ed. 1961, p. 155. 45. Vedi Gheorghe Caragaþã, Breve sguardo sullo sviluppo della letteratura romena, Roma, Istituto Europa Orientale, 1943, 24 pp.; Letteratura romena, 1955, Ed. Vallardi, coll. Istoria literaturilor strãine ale Europei ºi Americii. 46. A.N.S.C., Mpn, Propaganda, Dossier 1955, f. 1–6. 47. Vedi Petre Ciureanu, Corso di lingua romena, Genova, Casa Editrice “San Giorgio”, 1946, p. 511 (Univ. di Genova, Facoltà di Economia e Commercio); La poesia romena contemporanea, Genova, Di Stefano, 1944, p. 206; Saggi e ricerche su scrittori francesi, Genova, Editrice Italica, 1955. 48. Vedi Marina Vlasiu-Lupaº, Aspecte din istoria Transilvaniei, pref. di I. Moga, Sibiu, Institutul de Istorie Naþionalã, 1945. 49. A.N.S.C., Mcnc, Insegnamento Superiore, Dossier 2500/1943, f. 4. 50. Carmen Burcea, Despre romanisticã...cu patru filologi italieni, (intervista con Teresa Ferro, Roberto Scagno, Lorenzo Renzi, Alvaro Barbieri), in: „Litere, Arte, Idei”, anno VIII, No. 42 (298), 24 novembre 2003, p. 8. 51. Decreto no. 47/15 gennaio 2003 riguardante le onorificenze nazionale conferite a docenti italiani. Cf. M.O. no. 38/23 gennaio 2003. 52. H.G. no. 34 del 21 gennaio 1999 per la fondazione del’Istituto della Lingua Romena, M.O. no. 30 del 27 gennaio 1999. 53. Fondato in base alla Legge 356/11 luglio 2003, tramite la riorganizzazzione della Fondazione Culturale Romena. 54. Angela Tarantito, L’insegnamento del rumeno nel nuovo ordinamento didattico, in: Romania e Romània, Lingua e cultura romena di fronte all’Occidente, a cura di Teresa Ferro, Atti del Convegno Internazionale di Studi, Udine, 11–14 settembre 2002, p. 314. 55. Carmen Burcea, Filoromânii din “Portul Cocorilor”, in: “Curierul Românesc”, Anno XV, no. 4 (195), 2003, p. 26. I S P R I ’s A C A D E M I C L I F E TACKLING CONSERVATISM TODAY The conference took place at the Institute of Political Science and International Relations on the 24th of November 2005. The event started with the communication of Professor Ion Bulei, Ph. D., director of the institute, who mentioned the huge diversity of personalities that can be affiliated with contemporary conservatism — from Margaret Thatcher and Ronald Reagan, to the late John Paul II —, given the rich and wide range of characteristics and definitions for this wide cultural trend. First of all, the speaker has shown that conservatism stands against the idea that a personality or a group can offer the solutions to the complex problems of our modernity. The institutions are compelled to have better answers to such problems. It is not that freedom should be erased; it rather should be “dissolved” in a more institutionalized manner, in order to meet the challenges in (or posed to) society. From the very beginning it was stated the intriguing and important role of a dimension of the ethics of responsibility, that should be correlated with this topic of conservatism. Another characteristic of contemporary conservatism is the accent put on abiding the law, the only appropriate context for accepting the evolutionism and the experimentation of the new. A brief historical approach to the subject has served the purpose of underlining the various brands and tendencies of conservatism in time. E. Burke and the French Revolution were the most important “stations” of this intellectual “route”. The “journey” helped depict the proper context for a very important distinction for the future analyzes, that one between “conservatism” and “traditionalism”. The former is a phenomenon specific for modernity, a concept used both in history and sociology to refer to a modern historical phenomenon, and a political current with roots in the French Revolution, that was also a reaction to that revolution, as a political reformism (and conformism) with respect for the pragmatic, for present, for the facts, for property. The latter is a permanent human trait, a more psychological dimension in its nature. Preferred by M. Weber in his writings, it means the resistance to all that is new, the refusal to adhere to whatever is new. The speaker ended his presentation with the importance for the conservatism of the modern political institutions of the state, today. The evolution of conservatism as political philosophy, and as political practice in the last two decades, was the topic of the second conference, sustained by Gabriela Tãnãsescu, researcher at the Institute of Political Science and International Relations, the department of political philosophy. The assumption of this presentation was the powerful impact on the British political conservatism of the intellectual currents gathered under the label of the ample movement of the American New Right: the economic libertarianism, the social traditionalism and the antiCommunist militancy, the first two lacking unity and compatibility under the philosophical, political and doctrinaire aspects. The specific of the British conservatism under the Thatcher government, as that of the American conservatism promoted by the Reagan administration, was presented as the result of a process of adapting of the consecrated principles of conservatism to those of the New Right, and especially to the hegemony of the free market principle. The lever of adopting and applying by the agents of conservatism of such a mixture of classic liberalism and libertarianism — by the end of a stage of economic stagnation and social conflict in the case of Great Britain — was assuring a sustained rhythm for the development, and, especially in the case of the USA, also for the economic expansion. As an answer to globalization, the use of this (AngloSaxon) model of competitiveness and efficiency — considered as well the “engine” of the European Union, that is dominated by a quite different French and German model of social economy — considered a success in terms of economy, triggered the transformation of the British political culture. Until 1979 the political culture in the Great Britain was co-extensive with a cultural conservatism faithful to consolidated communities, to the intermediary institutions and to Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 109–120, Bucharest, 2005. 110 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 2 the shared values, but answering globalization it has became for the most part individualistic. The presentation analyzed the profound mutations suffered in the corporatist politics, in the macroeconomics of the “complete use of the labor force”, in the traditional forms of life, in the institutional heritage, and in the mechanism of reproducing cultural identity, in Britain, since 1979, too. In such an interpretation, the libertarian individualism adopted in the Great Britain under the government of M. Thatcher is considered to de-legitimize traditions and conventions central to the British culture and to undermine the “human post-war liberalism” (in the phrasing of John Gray), in the views of a Tory paternalist manifestation and in those of a more communitarian tradition, yet, adapted to the conditions of the industrial society of late modernity. The discussions brought forth the issue of differentiation between conservatism and neo-conservatism, “conservatory revolution” in Germany in the 20s and 30s (I. Goian), the relationship between post-liberalism and conservatism (F. Müller), the doctrinaire relaxation/elasticity of contemporary conservatism (G. Tãnãsescu, I. Bulei), the problematics of the third way in relationship with conservatism, the absence of conservatism in Romania, the orange revolutions as conservatory reformism (R. Iamandi), the difference of conservatism in developed countries and in less developed countries of perifery (I. Goian, H. ªerban). Henrieta ªerban FUTURE CONFERENCES The Japanese Political Science Association invites interested scholars to participate at the 20th World Congress of the International Political Science Association (IPSA) in Fukuoka, Japan. Join us for this stimulating meeting on the theme “Is Democracy Working?” that will be held from July 9 to 13, 2006. Main theme Sessions: Panels and special sessions related to the main theme will be grouped under 6 major sub-themes: • The crisis and capacity of democracy: Chair: DirkBerg-Schlosser. Comparative perspectives: panels in this section will seek to explore dissatisfaction with the functioning of established democracies, incorporating issues such as declining voter turnout, financial scandals, political cynicism, populist and extremist appeals; sub-types of “defective” democracies, such as “delegative”, illiberal, “clientelistic”, among others; criteria and measurements of the “quality” of democracy including transparency, accountability, and inclusiveness in democratic states; the capacity of democracy for conflict resolution in, for instance, multi-ethnic and multi-cultural societies; the prospects for further democratization in various regions of the world, including Central Asia, and the Middle East. • Democracy and the new world order: Chairs: Luc Sindjoun & Bertrand Badie. International relations analysis clearly excluded democracy from its vision. Structured by power politics, the international arena was construed as being free of any democratic concerns. This approach was challenged by wilsonian idealism, the position peace theory and then by the increasing trends of individuals and social actors to create a debate on, and participate in, international issues. In this Main Theme, our aim would be to evaluate the ability of democratic values and practices to reshape the international arena, and investigate the ways of democratization in IR. This process could imply a more effective participation of the weak or small states to the international concert, their growing capacity to balance the hegemonic powers, a better efficiency of multilaterialism, an increasing relevance of common goods in managing global governance, a more performant mobilization of non-state actors which would entail a higher level of social participation in the international decision-making processes, a monitoring function of the international public space on the state action and a fading role of the secrecy in IR. • Institutional legitimacy, interest representation and democratic practice Chair: Leonardo Morlino. Some of the classic topics in political science need to be revisited in the present era of change and diffusion of democratic practice. For established democracies, recently built democratic 3 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 111 regimes and transitional hybrid regimes, the key aspects still are legitimacy and representative actors. But they present new forms and ways of working in the contemporary democratic practice, where the role of supranational and international organizations also has to be taken into account. The panels may address either theoretical issues or empirical themes; they may be either comparative or centered on a case-study; they may be grounded in different approaches, methodologies or empirical techniques; however, they should give an idea of the depth of the change by covering a large span of time and should focus on the connections between legitimacy and representation in democratic practice. • Participation and the politics of identity Chair: Hideo Otake. In an era of neo-liberal ascendancy, we are witnessing the resurgence of various social movements, spearheaded by the anti-globalization movement and the protests against U.S. military intervention in Iraq. Other social movements, commonly called “new social movements” whose origins date from the late 1960s and 1970s, continue to play important roles in awakening public awareness and influence on governmental policy making in areas such as disability, ecology, gender, and ethnic minorities. In addition, extreme right groups are increasingly making themselves heard in the political process in many nations. Panels in this section are expected to address the causes and consequences of those social movements broadly defined, analyze their characteristics in comparison with the traditional social movements such as the trade union movement, and explore their relationship with established political parties (domestic as well as foreign), government institutions, and business corporations. Public policies, bureaucracies and the performance of democracy: Chair: Lourdes Sola. For various reasons uncertainty is inherent in public policy-making, especially in contemporary democracies — there is a normative dimension, as goals and standards of judgment are a matter of political preference and culture; criteria of performance are being reassessed in tandem with changing political relations and with learning processes prompted by globalization; policy-makers operate in an environment of increasingly “bounded rationality”, that is, with limited knowledge with reference to new actors and instutitional/technological innovations such as forms of ‘direct’ democracy, e.democracy, and others. In addition, integration of emerging market democracies into the global order creates serious constraints for the task of reconciling legitimacy and effectiveness as guiding principles: while local populations associate democracy with economic welfare, equality, and political stability, policy makers are bound to deliver public policies with an eye to financial credibility as well as to the electorate. “Good government” and “good governance” are thus reduced to simpler and often simplistic notions of “good economic management”. The panels in this section will take stock of much experimentation and theorizing, in order to reassess under which conditions democracy may be said to be an enabling constraint to the effectiveness and legitimacy of public policies. • Political Knowledge, Theory, and the Design of Democratic Institutions Chair: Henry Milner. Citizens’ knowledge of politics is a key component of democracy. Political theorists have long identified the possession of political information as a precondition for taking part in democratic decision-making. They have drawn our attention especially to elites blocking or distorting political knowledge. These continue to be important concerns. But what of the dissemination of political knowledge? We know that it is the informed citizen that votes and is civically engaged. Yet the informed participating citizen is proving elusive: empirical studies show a low and apparently declining level of political knowledge. But what do citizens in a democracy know — and need to know — about their political institutions and actors, and what is the role of the political science profession in this process? There is great need for comparative analyses that consider political knowledge from a variety of angles, empirically and theoretically. Brought together, such work can help both long-standing and new democracies to identify institutions and policies that affect, and thus potentially boost, political knowledge. Further informations regarding participations are available at the following web address: www.fukuoka2006.com 112 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 4 With a view to enhancing the quality and diversity of participation in its world congress, the IPSA has instituted a series of awards in the following categories: i. Karl Deutsch Award, ii. Stein Rokkan Fellowships, iii. Francesco Kjellberg Award, iv. IPSA travel grants, v. Special travel grants vi. IPSA Prize for Lifetime Achievement in Political Science Awarded by the Foundation Mattei Dogan. Lucian Jora CONFERENCES AND CALLS FOR PAPERS1 Please find below the details regarding the following events: — Summer School Berlin 2006 (Berlin,Germany) — The Streit Council for a Union of Democracies (Paper Competition) — 7th Biennial Conference of ECSA (Canada) (Victoria, Canada) — State, Conflict and Democracy Symposium (Lund, Sweden) — International Political Economy Society 1st Conference (Princeton, United States) — 3rd Prato International Community Informatics Conference (Prato, Italy) — Globalisation & Political Theory of Welfare State and Citizenship (Denmark) — 1st ECPR Graduate Conference (Essex, United Kingdom) Publications including calls for articles: — Journal of Contemporary European Research (new issue now online) — New UACES/Routledge Book Series “Contemporary European Studies” Jobs, Grants & Prizes: — PhD Fellowships: “Foreignness and Integration in the Baltic Region” (Germany) — Council for European Studies 2006 Fellowship Program (Columbia University, NY) — Research Assistants (x2) European University Institute (Florence, Italy) — Lecturer B/Senior Lecturer In Contemporary European Studies (Sussex, UK) — Australian European University Institute Fellowships Association Inc. Fellowships — Lecturer in Political Studies (University of Auckland, New Zealand) — 2006 PhD Prize, European Consortium for Political Research — “Sciences Po” Scholarship for Masters Program in Political Sciences — HEIRS Essay Prize 2006, History of European Integration Research Society — Graduate Teaching Scholarship (for PhD) (University of Glasgow, UK) — Erasmus Mundus Courses — Fellowships, European University Institute (Florence, Italy) Call for Papers: Summer School Berlin 2006, Berlin, Germany, 24–30 July 2006 Closes 1 January 2006 The Research Centre for East European Studies at the University of Bremen, together with the German Association for East European Studies in Berlin requests applications to an international Summer School on Justice as a societal and political matter. Equality, social and legal security as conditions for democracy and the market funded by the Volkswagen-Stiftung, Hannover. The Summer School: This conference is the first of three Summer Schools for young academics doing research on Eastern Europe. The Summer School “A Changing Europe” is a follow-up project of the Conferences of Young Experts on Eastern Europe (1995-2005) which provided the foundation 5 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 113 for a tight network of young researchers and other experts concerned with Eastern Europe and the social sciences. The Summer Schools aim at extending this concept to researchers in Central and Eastern Europe. Paper proposals: Paper proposals must be based on original research and should not exceed 200 words. They have to be drafted in English and outline the most important theoretical and empirical aspects of the planned contribution. Please include a short CV, information about institutional affiliation, status, address etc. In order to be selected it is of central importance to connect an empirical question with a theoretical approach and concept. Comparative approaches (inter-as well as intra-regionally) are encouraged. An international review panel will assess the papers for the conference in an anonymous review process. The deadline for receipt of paper proposals is 1 January 2006. Please submit your proposal to Dr. Sabine Fischer ([email protected] <mailto:[email protected]>). Costs: Funding by the Volkswagen-Stiftung covers travel costs as well as accommodation and conference fees. Location: The Summer School will take place at the Club House of the Freie Universitaet Berlin, Berlin-Dahlem, Goethe str. 49, near U-train station Krumme Lanke. Information: Further information about the Summer School as well as the conference project “A changing Europe” in general will be available from 1. December 2005 at www.changing-europe.de. Call for Papers: The Streit Council for a Union of Democracies, Paper Competition Inter-Democracy Integration and Federalism Closes 10 January 2006 Theme: Institutional Prerequisites for Effective Cooperation among Democracies Deadline for Papers: 10 January 2006 Eligibility: MA and PhD students in history, political science and international relations. We are inviting submission of proposals from MA and Ph. D. candidates on topics within the theme of the institutional prerequisites for furthering the integration of democracies internationally. We have a particular interest in papers that take a risk and put forward new approaches to foster closer cooperation among democracies, at the same time providing practical and theoretical grounding for their proposals. Further information on procedures for submitting papers is available online at: http://www.streitcouncil.org/main.cfm?r1=17.00&r2=2.00&ID=177&level=2 Papers for the competition should be submitted by January 10, 2006. to: [email protected] and copied to [email protected] For inquiries please contact: Dr. Tiziana Stella by email, [email protected] or check the website: http://www.streitcouncil.org. Amended Call for Proposals: 7th Biennial Conference of European Community Studies Association Canada (ECSA-C) “What Kind of Europe? Multiculturalism, Migration, Political Community and Lessons from Canada”, Victoria, Canada Friday 19 Saturday 20 May 2006 Closes 31 January 2006 Europe is going through fundamental and vital changes and faces new challenges. The future of the constitutional convention, the 2004 enlargement by 10 countries and the negotiations with four prospective new members have created unprecedented challenges. These challenges to governance include: the numbers of people migrating within and from without the EU, major social and cultural differences among those peoples, the geo-strategic importance and interests of the states of the enlarging EU, the new decision making procedures in the field of Justice and Home affairs, the need for trade policies which take into account the growth of new economic powers (China and India) and, last but not least, the new power relationships in the world. The ECSA-Canada Biennial will be held in Victoria to allow practitioners and researchers (professors and graduate students) to exchange views on the ramifications of these scenarios and momentous changes. Lawyers, political scientists, economists, historians, social 114 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 6 scientists, geographers, linguists and others from all over the world are invited to meet and present their views. If you wish to participate, please send by e-mail, a one-page summary of your proposed paper, together with a brief CV to both programme chairs, Dr. Edelgard Mahant (Mahant@glendon. yorku.ca), Dr. Emmanuel Brunet-Jailly ([email protected] ) Proposals for panels of related papers are also welcome. Panels should be composed of up to four related papers, and, if possible, a chairperson and a discussant. Subject to availability of funding, ECSA Canada can finance up to 50% of travel expenses of selected paper givers. Preference will be given to graduate students, postdocs, persons from Central and Eastern Europe, and others who can demonstrate financial need. The payment, at the discretion of ECSA-C, will be made only on presentation of the original tickets, receipts and boarding passes. Deadline for the submission of abstracts is 31 January 2006. Applicants will be informed of the acceptance (or otherwise) of their abstract during February 2006. State, Conflict and Democracy Symposium Lund University, Sweden 12–13 May 2006 Closes 31 January 2006 How can the interest of peace and democracy be jointly served in post-conflict processes of state-building and reconstruction? In practice, representatives of a range of international agencies and organizations have to deal with this question on a daily basis; theoretically, the literature addressing this question is sparse, disjointed, and unsystematic. With the support of the Bank of Sweden Tercentenary Foundation the undersigned are arranging a symposium on these issues. Papers are not a requirement for participation. However, three workshops will provide opportunities to present papers for those of you that are interested. There will be an opportunity to present a limited number of papers during the three workshops. It will also be possible to upload papers to this site. We envisage that all papers will be published, either as contributions to a special issue of a journal, or as conference proceedings. If you would like to present a paper or upload a paper, please provide an abstract of no more than 250 words by 31 January 2006. Send your abstract as an attachment to: [email protected] Information on the workshops and the call for papers can be found online at: www.svet. lu.se/conference/index.html International Political Economy Society, First Annual Conference Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey, United States, November 2006 Closes 1 February 2006 We write to announce the inaugural meeting of the International Political Economy Society (IPES), and to invite you to submit a proposal for a paper to be presented at the first annual conference to be held at Princeton University, 17–18 November 2006. Rationale: The purpose of this Society and conference is two-fold. First, we hope to highlight the best new work in international political economy and to promote this exciting field of research. Second, the larger association meetings (e.g., APSA, ISA) have grown somewhat diffuse. Following the example of several smaller societies that have developed in related fields, such as the Public Choice Society, Peace Sciences Society (International) and the International Society for New Institutional Economics, the conference will focus on a smaller number of carefully selected papers. With participants who share a common background and field expertise, we expect the quality of the presentations and discussions to be very high. Expenses: In addition to organizing and hosting the conference, the Center for Globalization and Governance has contributed limited amounts of money to help defray hotel expenses for those attendees who do not have travel funds of their own. Priority in distributing these funds will be given to graduate students and junior faculty presenting papers at the meeting. If you wish to be considered for these travel funds, please indicate this at the end of your paper proposal (see below). 7 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 115 Further information about registering for the conference and logistics (i.e., hotel reservations) will be forthcoming in May 2006 with the preliminary program and posted at our website (The website is available at http://polisci.ucsd.edu/ipes/). Proposals: For purposes of the conference, appropriate papers will include some international component (i.e., either the independent or dependent variable must be “international” in some meaningful sense), and should either focus on some area of economic policy or use economic methods to analyze political phenomena. Although we expect the conference to be centered on political scientists working on IPE, we would also welcome submissions from economists and other scholars from cognate fields. One important goal of IPES is to provide an outlet for up-andcoming IPE scholars to increase their visibility. For that reason we will give some priority to presentations by advanced graduate and recent Ph.D.’s. Nonetheless, proposals from scholars at all stages of their careers are encouraged. Proposals for papers should be submitted by 1 February 2006. Proposals need not be long, but should be sufficiently detailed to allow a full understanding of the contribution of the paper. Graduate students should also submit a letter of support from their dissertation advisors. All proposals will be vetted by the program committee. Participants will be notified by May 2006 and a preliminary program will be released at that time. Please submit your proposals to: [email protected] If you have any questions or concerns, please contact any of the committee members or write to us at [email protected] Call For Papers: Constructing and Sharing Memory — Community Informatics, Identity and Empowerment, 3rd Prato International Community Informatics Conference Prato, Italy October 2006 Closes 1 February 2006 We are seeking abstracts from academics, practitioners and PhD students for a conference and workshop event at the Monash University Centre, Prato, Italy, 9–11 October 2006. The Centre for Community Networking Research, Monash, in conjunction with the Community Informatics Research Network, has held highly successful events in 2003 and 2004 in Prato. The Prato campus is an exceptional environment in which to exchange ideas. The Centre is just off the main piazza of a small Tuscan city. It is close to Italian transport hubs. There are also a limited number of workshop slots available. If you believe that you can offer an engaging and relevant workshop, please submit a short proposal as soon as possible. If you have other innovative ideas for events at the conference, please don’t hesitate to contact us! Because of the likely strong demand for acceptance, your early submission is strongly encou aged. You are also encouraged to submit early to meet your accommodation needs. A draft program and further information on the conference topics as well as potential themes for papers and presentations can be found online at the conference website. A brochure for distribution and noticeboards can also be downloaded from the website. Contact: [email protected] Website: http://www.ccnr.net/prato2006 Globalisation and the Political Theory of the Welfare State and Citizenship International Conference - Aalborg University, Denmark May 2006 Closes 1 February 2006 The conference is organised by the Danish Network on Political Theory, Aarhus University, Department of History, International and Social Studies and Department of Economics, Politics and Public Administration, Aalborg University. The purpose of this conference is to analyse how Western welfare state values, citizenship and conceptual foundations are challenged by globalisation. Confirmed keynote speakers are: Professor Will Kymlicka (Queen’s University, Kingston, Canada) Professor Ruth Lister (Loughborough University, England) Professor Bryan Turner (University of Singapore, Singapore) Professor Jørgen Goul Andersen (Aalborg University, Denmark) 116 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 8 The conference is organised around four themes, which represent new challenges to Western we fare states and social and political citizenship: 1. The tension between trans-national politics, equality and social rights; 2. The tension between universalism and particularism; 3. The tension between citizenship rights and human rights; 4. The tension between welfare solidarity and migration. An overview of the conference and detailed information on the conference themes and registration can be found at the conference website: http://www.ihis.aau.dk/freia/ocs/index.php?cf=2 Abstracts: 300 word abstracts are due on 1 February 2006. Call for Papers: Panel Proposals 1st European Consortium for Political Research Graduate Conference University of Essex, United Kingdom September 2006 Closes 1 March 2006 Graduate students from ECPR member institutions are welcome to submit paper or full panel proposals for the first ECPR Graduate Conference. For further information, please see: http://www.essex.ac.uk/ecpr/events/graduateconference/index.aspx The call for papers can be found at: http://www.essex.ac.uk/ecpr/events/graduateconference/ call_papersandpanels.aspx Publications • “Journal of Contemporary European Research”, Volume 1 Issue 2 now available online The latest Issue of JCER: “Journal of Contemporary European Research” is now available online at http://www.jcer.net • New UACES/Routledge Book Series “Contemporary European Studies” The new UACES/Routledge book series “Contemporary European Studies” is inviting proposals for high quality research monographs in all sub-fields of European Studies. We are particularly keen to publish interdisciplinary research, but all proposals will be given serious consideration. For further advice and information, or to submit proposals, please contact one (or all) of the series editors: Tanja Boerzel ([email protected]) Michelle Cini ([email protected]) Alex Warleigh ([email protected]) Jobs, Grants & Prizes PhD Fellowships-Graduate Programme 619: “Contact Area Mare Balticum: Foreignness and Integration in the Baltic Region“ Closes 31 December 2005 In May 2006, the Ernst Moritz Arndt University, Greifswald, will continue the graduate programme “Contact Area Mare Balticum: Foreignness and Integration in the Baltic Region“, subject to final authorisation by the German Research Foundation. Its goal is to enhance students’ enthusiasm for the issue of foreignness and integration in the Baltic region, while training them in the skills required for a productive research career. The programme is designed for Ph.D. students in Philosophy, Political Sciences, Psychology, Scandinavian and Germanic Languages, Slavic Literatures, Baltic Languages and Literatures, Art History, History and Law, and examines foreignness as an intellectual, cultural and social phenomenon. Key questions are: foreignness in (Baltic) thought, and factors of integration, perception of foreigners/foreignness and cultural transformation in historical perspective. The graduate programme will award 12 Ph.D. fellowships. Fellows receive financial support in the form of scholarships of 1,000/month. In addition, every fellow will receive 103/month for books and other study materials. Fellowships are for two years in the first instance and they can be extended for one more year. To apply for a fellowship, please send your Curriculum Vitae copies of examination certificates (English or German translations). 9 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 117 Project Proposal (not to exceed 7 pages). Letter of Recommendation by a referee to the coordinator of the Graduate Programme: Professor Dr Michael, North Ernst Moritz Arndt University, Department of History, Chair of Modern History- Domstrasse 9 a D-17487 Greifswald Germany Additional information about the Graduate Programme is available in the Web: www.unigreifswald.de/~marebalt/Startseite.htm, by phone +49 (0)3834 86-3308 or mail [email protected]. Council for European Studies — 2006 Fellowship Program Closes 15 January 2006 Graduate students are invited to participate in the Council for European Studies 2006 Fellowship Program. The CES Fellowship Program has granted more than 500 awards over the last thirty-five years, providing doctoral students with the opportunity to travel to Europe to test the feasibility of their dissertation topics. The application must be received in the Council’s office via postal mail by 15 January 2006. The address is as follows: Council For European Studies-Columbia University, 420 West 118th Street, MC New York, NY 10027, United States of America. The 2006 application form can be downloading from our website http://www. councilforeuropeanstudies.org/awards/awards.html. Research Assistants(x2), Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies, European University Institute, Florence, Italy Closes 15 January 2006 Ref: RSC 12/2005 (please quote in all correspondence) Contract Details: Up to 4 years, start date to be agreed, but not later than 1 March 2006. Salary according to German Bat IIa/halbe (50% of full-time position, up to 19.25 hours/week, ca. 1,239 per month). Director of project: Prof. Dr. Adrienne Heritier (in collaboration with Prof. Dr. Tanja A. Boerzel / Free University Berlin) Title of project: “Fostering Regulation? Corporate Social Responsibility in Countries with Weak Regulatory Capacity”. The project is part of the Berlin-based Sonderforschungsbereich SFB 700 (see www.sfb700. fu-berlin.de in German). We are interested in research questions such as: To which degree do selfregulatory initiatives of Multinational Corporations (MNCs) or Public Private Partnerships (PPPs) that promote Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR) foster the regulative capacities in developing countries? Under which conditions do MNCs support the enforcement of state regulations? Which New Modes of Governance emerge thereby? Our Case Studies will be located in South Africa. (See for further project descriptions: http:// www.sfb700.fu-berlin.de/forschung/projektbereiche, in German); however, this Advertisement for two appointments of Research Assistant is not yet posted on the project’s website). Job description: Developing of questionnaire, collection of data, (mostly qualitative) data analysis, data interpretation, reporting of data, field research, literature analysis. Research Assistants are encouraged to work part time on a thematically related PhD project. Qualifications: You should have an excellent degree in Political or Social Science (M.A. or equivalent degree, like the German Diplom or Magister), training in theoretically guided qualitative (or quantitative) empirical research on governance, and a very good command of the English language. Applications with the usual documents — including a curriculum vitae — must be addressed to the Academic Service, for attention of Dr. A. Frijdal, at the following e-mail address: [email protected]. If you require specific information about the position, please contact Dr. Frijdal at [email protected]. The deadline for application is 15 January 2006. 118 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 10 Lecturer B/Senior Lecturer In Contemporary European Studies From 1 Sept 2006 (Ref 248) Sussex European Institute, University Of Sussex, United Kingdom Closes 20 January 2006 The Sussex European Institute wishes to make a permanent appointment at Lecturer B/Senior Lecturer level. The post will be at the core of SEI and entail involvement across SEI’s teaching and research activities and will contribute to managing these activities. You will have a research record and experience that shows your potential to be an authority in the field of European political integration. Depending on experience, you will have, or show the potential to develop, an outstanding research record with a focus on issues of direct policy concern, be an excellent teacher and supervisor, and have experience of, or show the potential to undertake, research management. Potential candidates are encouraged to speak to Professor Jim Rollo (01273 877265) or Professor Aleks Szczerbiak (01273 678443) Salary: £28,829 To £36,959 Or £38,685 To £43,850 PA Closing date: Friday 20 January 2006 Application details are available from and should be returned to the Human Resources Division, Sussex House, University of Sussex, Falmer, Brighton, BN1 9RH. Tel 01273 678706, Fax 01273 877401, email [email protected]. Details of all posts can be found via the University website: www.sussex.ac.uk/jobs Fellowships, Australian European University Institute, Fellowships Association Inc. Florence, Italy Closes 25 January 2006 Applications are now invited for Australian European University Institute Fellowships which provide the opportunity to carry out research for three months at the European University Institute in Florence. Two postgraduate Fellowships will be offered for the period September–December 2006. (Please note: a six-month postdoctoral Fellowship will be advertised from 25 March 2006 for January–June 2007). The postgraduate Fellowships are available to postgraduates currently undertaking research in history, law, economics, and social and political sciences who are at an advanced stage of their research and are able to identify a direct benefit for their research from a period of residence at the EUI. The Fellowships cover EUI fees for three months and provide a one-off payment of $7,000 to contribute to travel and subsistence. The successful candidates will also have access to the facilities of the Monash University Prato Centre and are encouraged to participate in its activities, and at the conclusion of the award period, will have the opportunity to present a paper at the Monash University London Centre. All applications are to be emailed to [email protected] Further information on the AEUIFAI is available at: http://www.arts.monash.edu.au/history/ aeuifai; on the European University Institute at: http://www.iue.it/; and on the Monash University Prato Centre at http://www.ita.monash.edu/; or from the Secretary, Dr. Peter Howard, e-mail: [email protected]. Applications close 25 January 2006. (The successful applicants will be notified by mid-May 2006). Lecturer in Political Studies, Department of Political Studies University of Auckland, New Zealand Closes 27 January 2006 The Department of Political Studies is seeking to appoint a permanent academic position in international relations at the lecturer level. We wish to appoint someone whose work is theoretically informed and contributes to the study of a) world politics with a focus on conflict and security issues and/or b) the politics of regional integration, with a focus on Europe. The successful candidate(s) for these positions would be expected to teach in at least two of the following areas: international political economy, global governance, international security, 11 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 119 and/or the European Union. Successful candidates will be expected to take up their positions by 1 July 2006. Qualifications: PhD in Political Science; experience in lecturing to large classes would be an advantage. Enquiries of an academic nature should be directed to Professor Jack Vowles, Department of Political Studies, telephone 64-9-373 7599 ext 88644, email: [email protected]. 2006 PhD Prize European Consortium for Political Research Closes 31 January 2006 The deadline for nominations for the 2006 PhD Prize is 31 January 2006. Please note that the guidelines for nominations and the judging procedures have been updated to make the prize more accessible for candidates whose theses are written in languages other than English. Please see the web site for more information: http://www.essex.ac.uk/ecpr/funding/prizes. HEIRS Essay Prize 2006 History of European Integration Research Society Closes 31 March 2006 The History of European Integration Research Society is launching its Essay Prize Competition 2006. This year we especially encourage contributions from all post-graduate students and young researchers that tie European integration history to any aspect of the Cold War broadly defined. The winning essay will be submitted for publication in the journal Cold War History, published by the Taylor & Francis Group and housed by the LSE Cold War Studies Centre. The winning paper will be published after having gone through the peer-review procedure. Papers will be short-listed by the HEIRS Committee and the best four papers will be forwarded to a panel of leading historians. For this year’s competition, the judges are: Prof. Gérard Bossuat (Université de Cergy-Pontoise), Prof. Robert Gildea (University of Oxford), Dr Piers Ludlow (London School of Economics) and Prof. Wolfgang Schmale (Universität Wien). The deadline for submission is Friday, 31 March 2006. Manuscripts should be submitted in rich text format as an email attachment to [email protected]. The result will be announced on Monday, 15 May 2006 and publication will take place in due course. Format and style: All manuscripts must be written in English or in French. While under consideration for the HEIRS Essay Prize, papers should not be under consideration for any other publication. If another version of the article is under consideration by another publication, or has been, or will be published elsewhere, authors should clearly indicate this at the time of submission. Manuscripts should be between 7,000 and 10,000 words (including endnotes and references). The article should begin with an abstract of around 100 words, which should describe the main arguments and conclusions. To facilitate the typesetting process, notes should be grouped together at the end of the file. A short biographical note of around 50 words (including the author’s institutional affiliation and current and forthcoming projects) should be submitted in a separate file. In addition, full contact details (including postal address), any acknowledgements, and a note of the exact length of the article should be included in that file. It will be the authors’ responsibility to ensure that where copyright materials are included within an article the permission of the copyright holder has been obtained. Confirmation of this should be included with the submission. Graduate Teaching Scholarship (for PhD) University of Glasgow Glasgow, Scotland, United Kingdom Closes 1 May 2006 The Department of Politics University of Glasgow (rated 5 in the last 3 RAEs) will offer ONE Graduate Teaching Scholarship commencing in September 2006. Value: Home/EU fee waiver (c£3500) plus £2000 contribution to maintenance, for three years. The scholarship is open to non UK/EU students but there will be a fee short-fall, which may be met via other funds such as ORS (see below). 120 ISPRI’s ACADEMIC LIFE 12 Eligibility: a) Candidates must first have been accepted by the Department to do a Ph.D, that is, they must have been judged to possess [i] the requisite standard of qualifications [ii] a doctoral research topic that falls within the capacious remit of the Department to supervise (including EU politics and policy). In their application to undertake research they should indicate their desire to be considered for one of the scholarships. b) Candidates will typically possess a Masters degree (or equivalent) or be expected to complete one in 2005/6. c) Candidates will be expected to apply for funded scholarships (such as ESRC, AHRC, ORS and including those offered by the Faculty of Law, Business and Social Sciences, University of Glasgow). If successful the candidate must accept such an award. d) Candidates must, in the judgment of the Department, be able satisfactorily to offer seminar teaching, primarily at pre-honours (years 1 & 2) level. e) The closing date for applications is 1 May 2006 (later applications may be considered and placed on a “reserve”). Terms & Conditions: a] Scholars will undertake teaching allocated up to but not exceeding 6 hours a week, averaged across the academic year. b) The award of the scholarship in years 2 and 3 is dependent on a positive report of the annual progress review. c) Termination of studies will result in termination of the scholarship. d) Suspension of studies will normally lead to suspension of payments. Erasmus Mundus Courses Various Institutions, deadlines vary according to course The Erasmus Mundus programme is a co-operation and mobility programme in the field of higher education which promotes the European Union as a centre of excellence in learning around the world. It supports European top-quality Masters Courses and enhances the visibility and attractiveness of European higher education in third countries. It also provides EU–funded scholarships for third country nationals participating in these Masters Courses, as well as scholarships for EUnationals studying in third countries. Students interested in applying for Erasmus Mundus courses can check out the Erasmus Mundus programmes at the European Commission’s website: http:// europa.eu.int/comm/education/ programmes/ mundus/ projects. Further information on eligibility and conditions and Frequently Answered Questions are available at: http://europa.eu.int/comm/education/programmes/mundus/index_en.html Fellowships at the European University Institute, Florence, Italy The European University Institute in Florence, Italy, offers three different fellowship programmes: Max Weber Fellowships for junior post-docs who would like to embark on an academic career and improve their teaching and professional skills. Jean Monnet Fellowships at the Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies with its emphasis on research for junior academics at an early stage in their professional careers. Senior Fellowships for established academics with an international reputation for short stays of up to ten months in one of the Institute’s four departments. Further information and online application materials are available at http://www.iue.it/Servac/ Postdoctoral/>http://www.iue.it/Servac/Postdoctoral/ For queries please contact: [email protected]. NOTE 1. Courtesy of : Contemporary Europe Research Centre (CERC) at The University of Melbourne. Lucian Jora BOOK REVIEWS Francesco Guida Romania, Roma, Casa Editrice Edizioni Unicopli, 2005, 312 p. É stato pubblicato di recente un eccellente libro: Romania, stampato alla Casa editrice Edizioni Unicopli di Roma, sulla collana Storia d’Europa nel XX secolo, diretta da Marco Gervasoni e Leonardo Rapone. L’autore del volume è Francesco Guida, professore ordinario di Storia dell’Europa orientale presso la Facoltà di Scienze Politiche dell’Università di Roma Tre, segretario generale dell’Associazione Italiana Studi sul Sud/Est Europeo. Francesco Guida è uno storico ormai consacrato. Fin’ora ha scritto dei volumi come: La Bulgaria dalla Guerra di liberazione sino al trattato di Neuilly (1877/1919), Testimonianze italiane (Roma, 1984); L’Italia e il Risorgimento balcanico (Roma, 1984), Nascita di uno stato balcanico (si tratta di Bulgaria) (Napoli, 1988), Il leone e la scimitarra (Cosenza, 1990), Mezzo secolo di socialismo reale. L’Europa centro-orientale dal secondo conflitto mondiale all’era post/comunista (Torino, 1997), Russia ed Europa orientale 1815/1914 (Roma, 2003). L’elenco potrebbe continuare ancora, senza nemmeno accennare né tutti suoi libri, né i numerosi articoli e gli studi. Tale lavoro lo reputa come uno storico molto rigoroso, serio, in cui s’individua una laboriosità invidiabile. La storiografia sulla Romania aveva bisogno da molto tempo di uno storico italiano preoccupato dalle vicende romene, di un loro inquadramento nella situazione della storia europea, vista come una storia allo stesso tempo balcanica, parte dell’Europa orientale ma soprattutto parte dell’Europa intera. Quest’ultimo volume racconta la storia della Romania nel Novecento. Il racconto é suddiviso secondo una scansione ormai tradizionale e condivisa dagli storici. Tutto si sviluppa, fatto storico acanto fatto storico e le interpretazioni di questi fatti, svellendo pian-piano (il libro ha 350 pagine) una storia quasi sconosciuta dal pubblico italiano, assaltato ultimamente da una valanga dei fatti provenienti dall’Europa orientale. Comincia con una breve premessa dedicata al secolo precedente, poi tratta la Romania fino alla prima Guerra mondiale e la partecipazione del paese alla Grande Guerra (le prime battaglie, l’abbandono della Valacchia, l’armistizio, la pace separata, il ritorno in campo e la Guerra con l’Ungheria per la Transilvania e Banato). Molte pagine sono dedicate alla grand’unione del 1918/1919 che creò la Grande Romania, ai nuovi confini del paese nel contesto internazionale, alla Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 121–126, Bucharest, 2005. questione ebraica, alla questione del Danubio, al problema agrario, alla riforma elettorale e agli sviluppi politici nell’immediato dopoguerra, ai problemi di politica estera, del nazionalismo e alla posizione degli intellettuali, alla crisi politica del dopoguerra, alla storia politica, sociale, economica e culturale della Romania tra le due guerre mondiali. L’autore spiega tanto la democrazia mimata che la democrazia guidata esistenti in Romania fra le due guerre e come si arriva alle dittature di Carol II e di Antonescu. Poi, la seconda Guerra mondiale, con tutte le sue vicende che riguardano anche la Romania occupa una parte importante nel libro. Durante la Guerra, la Romania, come l’Italia, comincia le operazioni militare accanto ai tedeschi per finire la guerra accanto agli Alleati. L’autore si occupa poi della nascita del regime comunista (la questione della Transilvania, il terrore, le Chiese e il regime, la sovietizzazione della Romania, le purghe, gli intellettuali e il regime), della destalinizzazione alla dittatura di Ceusescu (scrive qui dell’eresia romena, della sua politica di quasindependenza nelle strutture militare e politiche est europee, Il Comecom e il Patto di Varsavia). La dittatura personale di Ceausescu è largamente spiegata e analizzata. Uno spazio generoso è accordato alla rivoluzione romena di dicembre 1989 e ai fatti storici seguenti (La Romania postcomunista, la questione della Moldavia, come excomunisti hanno ceduto lentamente il passo e perché è successo così). Sono pagine ben scritte, da un intellettuale occidentale che conosce intimamente la nostra storia e sa inquadrala nella storia regionale ed europea. Suo discorso è veramente europeo, privo di pregiudizi e di problemi di sentimentalismo nazionale, presenti di solito agli storici quando scrivono della storia del loro popolo. Un’appendice con capi di Stato e di governo, una bibliografia breve, ma ben scelta e un indice dei nomi completa un’opera di un grande valore e di una grande attualità. Non dobbiamo dimenticare che in Italia si conoscono pochissime cose sulla Romania e quello che si sa di solito é sbagliato. Abbiamo aspettato a lungo uno storico come Francesco Guida. E finalmente lui è arrivato. L’opera di Francesco Guida diventerà presto un punto di riferimento esenziale per tutti quelli che vogliono conoscere la Romania. Non solo il suo destino storico, ma anche il luogo della Romania nella nuova Europa. Ion Bulei 122 BOOK REVIEW 2 Angela Botez Un secol de filosofie româneascã, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei Române, 2005, 488p. This is a history of Romanian philosophical ideas, themes and personalities opened towards the “universal” and towards the ultimate “other” who is nowadays the Romanian unaware of her/his own philosophical thesaurus. The volume capitalizes on both the roots and on the opennings represented by the thought of the various figures of the Romanian philosophy in the 20th century. In this book, Romanian philosophy is depicted through the lenses of the contemporary elements of philosophical thought. Dusting “old” ideas, embracing them in the actual terms of appreciation — and not merely tailoring them fashionably — this is a work of unification of valuable theories and ideas, in times of celebrating diversity and difference, under such contemporary themes and within the contemporary cultural and philosophical paradigms in philosophy. Such a titanic effort starts by both understanding and highlighting the larger spiritual Romanian paradigm within which the cultural and philosophical one is inscribed. The author therefore identifies a stylistical matrix of the Romanian philosophy characterized by: (1) the reception of the main European philosophical currents, in a well-balanced and complementary-holistic perspective that puts the accent both on the German (Kant and Nietzsche) and on the French (Descartes and Bergson) philosophy, (2) the critique of the tendencies that claim themselves as the ultimate direction in philosophy — the logicist, the scientist, the empirist, the intuitionalist or the irrationalist. Each time a Romanian philosopher enrolles in a tendency, it is a nuanced affiliation, as this attempt is accompanied by certain specifications; and, (3) there are certain themes and disciplines where the Romanian authors have tried with predilection their competencies — metaphysics, the history of philosophy, gnoseology, the philosophy of logics, the philosophy of science, the philosophy of conscience or the philosophy of culture — although the other philosophical areas are not completely ignored. Thus, the Romanian philosophers are expressing a serius of “integrative” concepts and themes some “inedite” — for example Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru with the “energetic personalism”, Ion Petrovici with his “psycho-physical parallelism”, Constantin Noica with the “becoming into being”, Mircea Florian with the “theory of the given”, Lucian Blaga with the “ecstatic rationalism” etc. — and some perceiving culture as an “energetic mutation” (Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru ), or as an “psychical mutation” (Mihai Ralea), or, yet, as an “ontological mutation” as Lucian Blaga. Some of the Romanian philosophers have created their own philosophical method, like did Ion Petrovici (“the empirical and rationalist method”), Mircea Florian (“the method of recessivity”), Lucian Blaga (“the transfigurated antinomy” and “the categorial duality”), Petre Andrei (“the retotalizing capitalization”), Mihai Ralea (“the cognitive hesitation”), D.D. Roºca (“the existentialist negation”), or Emil Cioran (“nihilistic decomposure”). The contents of the volume follows these above mentioned characteristic lines. The introduction describes in the first part the stylistic matrix of the Romanian philosophy, the specificity of the history of the Romanian philosophy and the manner of the writing the volume. In the second part of the introduction there are a few important mentions dedicated to each of the Romanian creator of language and of philosophical school — Mihai Eminescu, Titu Maiorescu, Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru and Nae Ionescu. The first part of the book consists of nine chapters. The first chapters dedicated to the metaphysics of the 20th century tackles the orientations and their main figures of reference — Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru, Mircea Florian, Ion Petrovici, Nae Ionescu, Mircea Vulcãnescu — and the postmodern resurection of metaphysics occasioned by the integrative metaphysical concepts identified by the author in the work of Lucian Blaga. The second chapter confronts the reader with the Romanian Kantianism — Ion Petrovici, P.P. Negulescu, Constantin RãdulescuMotru, Mircea Florian and others — while discussing in a separate section the role and scope of the philosophy of science and logic in the Romanian culture. The philosophy of mind and consciousness is approached in the third chapter through a discussion of historical sources and contemporary conceptions in this field, complemented by the Romanian perspectives brought about by the representatives: Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru, Mircea Florian, Ion Petrovici, Mihai Ralea, Camil Petrescu and others. The next dimension approached in the book is holism and complemetary systemism, developed with a take on the holistic system and paradigm in the philosophy of the 20th century and on the approaches of the Romanian philosophers — ªtefan Lupaºcu, Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru, D.D. Roºca, Mihai Ralea, P.P. Negulescu, Petre Andrei, Lucian Blaga, Octav Onicescu, Mircea Florian. The subject is complemented by the study Mircea Eliade on Hermeneutics and Planetary Humanism. The fifth chapter tackles realism and its forms, in two parts: general perspectives and an investigation of realism and “recessivity” at Mircea Florian. The next chapter deals with matters of phenomenology and with the philosophy of language their trends and methodologies and their representatives amongst the Romanian philosophers: Constantin Floru, Camil Petrescu, Constantin Noica, and I.D. Gherea. The crisis of modernist philosophy is debated in the chapter seven of the first part, starting with the investigation of the rise of post-modernism and of the 3 BOOK REVIEW post-analytic epistemology and continuing with the analysis of integral rationality — as an “act of consciousness, not axiom of science” — of the hegelianism and of the existentialism at D.D. Roºca. The next subject is “Relativism and ContextualHistoricist Philosophy”, met in its orientations and main trends and complemented by the study ªtefan Lupaºcu — Post-analytic Originated Philosopher of Science. The last chapter of the first part is entitled Postmodernism and Nihilism, with a first study of the crisis of historicism and modern representationalism and a second on Emil Cioran — A Deconstructive Philosophy. The entire book is loaded with information.1 In a very “beyondist” manner the information is either explicitly or implicitly, according to the case, sustained by the “stories” (her, his and their) challenging the hegemonic genealogies of knowledge and power with whatever the sources such as the memories or the interviews, enriching the thought with subjectivity, whenever possible. While the first part places the accent on the intriguing Romanian philosophical ideas in the family of contemporary philosophical ideas and in relationship with the main philosophical trends, the second part offers a “diary” of the life of the far reaching Romanian contemporary philosophical community — chapter 1, “A Century of Romanian Philosophical Journalism”, chapter 2, “Philosophical Publications. Main Books”, chapter 3 “Philosophical Community. Associations and Institutes of Philosophy” and chapter 4, “Romanian Participation to Philosophy Congresses”. “As a Conclusion. Perspectives of Romanian Philosophers on National Identity and the specificity of Romanian Philosophy” defines a topic especially interesting for the realm of political philosophy. A. Botez says: “Without sustaining that we have a constituted and developed ethnic-psychology, given — among other factors — the fracture of the Romanian culture produced by the repressive and Stalinist communism, we can still state that there is in the Romanian philosophical, scientific, literary, journalistic writing, several theoretical perspectives of great value, many ‘esseistic’ points of view, relevant connotations, many scattered in public conferences, academic discourses, printed press articles. They all compose a picture worthy of contemporary interest, because they highlight a series of psychological constants of the Romanian people, legitimating a new reflection and a new investigation of the moral and spiritual physionomy of our kind.”2 But in order to identify only the crucial benefits of this volume, merely in a punctual manner, one has to acknowledge first of all the trait of Romanians “nihilist and cioranian” in nature, but lacking the talent and the depth of Cioran. The habit of minimizing the performances of the forerunners is especially damaging. It is one of the ‘refuges’ for personal misfortune, along with the trouble of being born Romanian and the shortcomings of the system. 123 Especially young people try to ignore and deny the substance of a Romanian philosophy before even starting to get the feel of it. For our young philosophers and theorists, such an incursion into the best of our philosophical not so distant past might be opening brighter future horizons. This is a chance for an entire range of diverse readers to find about the scope and the importance of the philosophical writings of personalities such as Lucian Blaga, Constantin Floru, Camil Petrescu, I.D. Gherea, ªtefan Lupaºcu, and D.D. Roºca or Mircea Florian, Ion Petrovici, Mihai Ralea and Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru and go hence beyond the fashionable works and present-day popular culture consideration of Constantin Noica, Mircea Eliade, Petre Þuþea3 and Emil Cioran. From this perspective, this work pays homage to the main Romanian creators of language and schools of philosophy: Mihai Eminescu, Titu Maiorescu, Constantin Rãdulescu-Motru and Nae Ionescu. The first two contributed essentially to the status of philosophy as a critical school. Eminescu, for instance, was offering the following definition for philosophy: “Philosophy has a critical value, it enhances the intellect, it breaks the laziness of meditation, and from exaggeratedly trusting foreign ideas it brings the intellect to the habit of investigating things in a genetic manner and weighting each word before including it into a theory”.4 Maiorescu has transformed this philosophical incentive into a norm. “If Maiorescu has created a critical school, and Rãdulescu-Motru a psychological one, around Nae Ionescu was erected such a philosophical school that triggered the names of C. Floru, Onicescu, Cioran, Eliade”.5 Both Eminescu and Maiorescu are evaluated here as precursors of the “Enlightened century”, marked by the rationalist and scientific school of C. RãdulescuMotru and by the intuitionist, anti-positivist and antilogicist school of Nae Ionescu, with personalities such as Lucian Blaga and Constantin Noica (exemplary personality through his paideical activity). With Nae Ionescu, the philosophical truth is one of many, the metaphysics a continuous confrontation with the self and reality which brings about relativity, Mircea Eliade highlights the fact of religion as a communicative experience that becomes fundamental for culture, as a nisus formativus, while Mircea Vulcãnescu sees a philosophy of Christianity central for aspiring at the metaphysical truth. Emil Cioran designed the search for absolute as the recipe for bringing the individual to the brink of despairing and saw the “small” cultures, doomed to live tragically against the “big” cultures. Constantin Noica remains for the attempt to infusing subjectivism and descriptive hermeneutics into metaphysics and Vasile Bãncilã brings a postmodernist air to contemporary Romanian philosophy sustaining that the philosophical essay is still literature. The volume brings all the readers to the “bigger picture”, the integrative one. “The universality of philosophy is expressed through particular creations and works”.6 124 BOOK REVIEW 4 NOTES 1. To better understand the extent of this informative approach one has to look not merely at the number of pages or at the complex structure of the contents, but also at the great variety of illustrations and at the extent of the selected bibliography. 2. Angela Botez, Un secol de filosofie româneascã, Bucureºti, Editura Academiei Române, 2005, p. 454. 3. Þuþea is considered as well by the author although she does not dedicate a distinct study to investigate his works, published after his death. “A certain type of peri-pathetical school has entertained also Petre Þuþea, followed by his disciples in his walks through Ciºmigiu public garden. He was a “machinery” spontaneously debiting aphorisms…”(p. 87). 4. Ibidem, p. 41. 5. Ibidem, p. 91. 6. Ibidem, p. 10. Henrieta ªerban Angela Botez Postmodernismul în filosofie, Bucureºti, Editura Floare albastrã, 2005, 352 p. This daring and informative work attunes the most important Romanian preoccupations in postmodern philosophy with the postmodern conversations of the world, at the same time, integrating these two dimensions in the general interest for contemporary knowledge and society. This example of scholarship and sound philosophical investigation is structured in five chapters, complemented by a list of works and scientific communications of the author, an extended bibliography and several pages of portraits of postmodern philosophers and postmodern philosophy books. The first chapter sets the frame for discussing postmodernism in philosophy. This volume tackles the “exploits” of postmodernism starting from the bibliography of postmodernism as sketched by Deborah Madsen, from the definitions of postmodernism as considered by Linda Hutcheon and from the postmodern themes and concepts (at D. Harvey and J.R. Watson). In the second chapter Angela Botez finds the historical sources of postmodernism in certain aspects of the philosophy of Socrates, Plato, Hegel, Spengler, Dewey, Peirce, Dilthey. The authors responsible for the major “turns” in philosophy are presented as forerunners, while the schools present the protagonists of postmodernism. Thus, the French school is present here with medallions of Derrida, Foucault, Lyotard, Lacan, Levinas, and Deleuze. Rorty, Paul de Man, Schrag, Sallis, Heelan, Ramsey represent the American school. The main representative of the Italian school is Vattimo. For the British school the selected representatives are Polanyi and Norris. Aside from such a classification of postmodernism, another dimension is suggested through the postmodern feminism investigated mainly at Arendt, Irigaray and Kristeva. The postmodern perspectives in philosophy are situated in a “metaphorical and symbolic space”, between modernity and postmodernity. From this specific situation the perspectives opened by the author are: realism and postmodernism, Kantianism and postmodernism, the metaphysics and its postmodern resurrection, postmodernism and its renewed epistemology, the critical (postmodern) approach to esthetics, postmodernism and religion. The Romanian authors included in the postmodern paradigm show the signification for present-day philosophy of selected, most important, Romanian philosophers. Emil Cioran is therefore present in the volume with a philosophy of deconstruction. Lucian Blaga is investigated in an original key, concerning the elements he developed for a postmodern resurrection of the metaphysics. ªt. Lupaºcu is capitalized as a postanalitic philosopher of science. D.D. Roºca is interpreted as a promoter of the cognitive pluralism and postanalitic contextualism. M. Eliade is explored for his hermeneutic method and for the notion of “planetary humanism” that he proposes and develops. Textualism and postmodern thought as literature are the aspects explored at Ion Barbu. Vasile Tonoiu represents the postmodern dialogism, the theory and practice of the dialogical person. The contemporary approaches of postmodern philosophy in Romania are as well presented, as echoed by “Revista de filosofie”, but not exclusively, in order to portray the aria of Romanian postmodern preoccupations in terms of names, articles, books, reviews, translations. The section of interviews is opened by the interview with J. Derrida where he characterizes himself as a product of human generosity, as a feminist, a child (with memories of the wise old man, who the young Derrida was, of the young 72 years old, as of the 32 years old debutante). Vattimo describes himself in dialogue with M. Mincu as the author of Dialettica, differenza et pensiero debole (1978) concepts — dialectics, difference and the “weak” thought — that 5 BOOK REVIEW he pursued in investigating throughout his entire work. Mary B. Hesse outlines the renewed epistemology of knowledge and a constructive critique of the standard theory of language that used to sustain the uniqueness of meaning and the pure deductive style in the philosophical argumentation. C. Norris answers as well Angela Botez in the volume, explaining his interest in postmodernism — deconstruction, metaphor, difference, the vague, the hermeneutic circle, the irony, the linguistic turn, the alterity — but also, the relationship among cuantics, realism and anti-realism. Steven Earnshaw, also in interview with A. Botez, shows that his works are centered on preoccupations for the esthetics, interpretation, meaning, culture and knowledge. He is willing to consider the “idea” of postmodernism a certain type of humanism. David M.K. Levin starts with an interest in the phenomenology of Merleau- 125 Ponty, but generally takes an interest in the contemporary continental philosophy with an appreciation of the American school (R. Rorty, H. Putnam, R. Brandom, C. Korsgaarti, T. Nagel — all considered analytical philosophers). From such structured philosophical stands the difficulty of pinpointing the complexity, the innovations and the dynamics of postmodernism is answered to its best. Postmodernism pursues knowledge and takes further the critical traditions of modernism in deconstructing the essentialism, fundationalism, positivism and representationalism sustained by modernism in philosophy. This volume captures not only the deconstructivist attempt, but also the integrative aspects of the reform brought about by postmodernism in contemporary philosophy, leaving behind the less constructive lament about the “universal abandon”. Henrieta ªerban Carmen Burcea Diplomaþie culturalã. Prezenþe româneºti în Italia interbelicã, Bucureºti, Institutul Cultural Român, 2005, 164 p. L’Institut Culturel Roumain propose au public un livre — Diplomatie culturelle. Présences roumaines dans l’Italie de l’entre-deux-guerres — qui reconstitue les efforts et les profils humains et professionnels des intellectuels italiens et roumains qui ont essayé de construire entre les deux pays une liaison permettant la connaissance réciproque des deux peuples apparentés, et le complètement des moyens politiques de diplomatie avec des moyens culturels. L’étude est centrée sur la manière où dans l’Italie de l’entre-deux-guerres les intellectuels roumains ont mis les fondements de certaines structures institutionnelles destinées à promouvoir la langue, la littérature, la culture roumaines. Tel que l’auteur le souligne, dans l’ensemble de la diplomatie culturelle, l’enseignement réciproque des langues constitue un élément central. C’est la plus sure méthode de rendre accessible une culture, étrangère. Et l’accessibilité assure la connaissance, ce qui est utile lorsqu’il s’agit de promouvoir les intérêts politiques d’un pays. C’est un des aspects qui mettent en évidence le rapport subtile qui existe entre la politique et la culture, et la fonction que la propagande accomplit: “Propagande, diplomatie culturelle, stratégie d’image sont des termes ayant un haut degré d’équivalence entre eux, mais aussi des différences de nuance. Ces termes désignent un composant vraiment relévant dans la complexité des relations internationales. La dichotomie du concept suppose une complémentarité entre deux éléments — la politique et la culture — dont la force est agrandie par un troisième élément: la propagande. Dans cette équation la culture est la couverture attractive de la politique, et la propagande est l’instrument qui assure leur cohésion” (p.11). Pour obtenir les données qui sont valorisées dans ce livre, Carmen Burcea a utilisé beaucoup de fonds documentaires, couvrant la période de l’entre-deuxguerres jusqu’aux années 1946–1947, c’est-à-dire jusqu’au changement de régime politique. De ces archives accessibles, Carmen Burcea a extrait des informations sur la vie quotidienne des intellectuels roumains qui ont fait un but de leur désir de promouvoir la spiritualité roumaine en Italie. Il s’agit des professeurs qui ont institutionnalisé l’enseignement du roumain en Italie, qui ont réalisé des traductions pour mettre en relief la richesse de la littérature roumaine, qui se sont entourés d’étudiants italiens intéressés à une culture avec laquelle ils identifiaient des similitudes, qui ont souligné les interférences entre les deux cultures, italienne et roumaine, qui ont publié dans les revues italiennes des articles et des études pour prouver la passion et la ténacité de leur travail. Dans cet effort, on ne peut rester indifférent aux difficultés que ces intellectuels ont connues: les sacrifices matériels, la pauvreté des ressources allouées à leur effort par les autorités roumaines — on invoque surtout le Ministère de l’Éducation et celui de la Propagande —, le manque d’articulation de cette activité de diplomatie culturelle par comparaison à celle développée par les Hongrois, qui était plus pénétrante et suivait un but politique précis, lié au territoire de Transylvanie, présenté en tant que partie intégrante de la Hongrie historique. La dimension humaine de ces intellectuels résulte des détails qui décrivent ces difficultés. On ne 126 BOOK REVIEW passe pas de vue les rivalités entre ces intellectuels, rivalités qu’on ne doit ni condamner ni justifier: elles faisaient partie d’un ensemble de relations personnelles et professionnelles. On insiste sur les profils de Claudiu Isopescu ou Th. Solacolu, dont la rivalité a beaucoup nourri la correspondance des deux avec leurs amis. On présente un entier «réseau» qui divisait ce milieu intellectuel en amis et ennemis, milieu centré autour de grandes personnalités telles que Nicolae Iorga ou Nicolae Titulescu. On met aussi en évidence les limites et les erreurs qui ont été faites par ces intellectuels: Eliade par exemple critique le travail de Claudiu Isopescu d’enseigner le roumain et de faire traduire, par ses étudiants italiens connaisseurs du roumain, certaines oeuvres littéraires roumaines, et il met en discussion les critères de sélection des oeuvres à traduire et le manque d’un projet à ce sujet. Mais, ces limites sont à leur tour facilement explicables, surtout si l’on prend en considération les ressources financières réduites et un certain manque d’organisation des autorités roumaines vis-à-vis de la propagande en Italie. Un espace que les intellectuels, esprits éclairés de l’époque, ne voulaient pas perdre en faveur de la propagande hongroise, mieux organisée et qui profitait au manque d’information pour imposer sa réalité historique et géographique. La lecture du livre nous présente les données concrètes mesurant cette différence d’organisation et d’efficacité entre les deux propagandes. Le livre est structuré en quelques parties: La propagande roumaine en Italie; les Lettorati —centres de cultures; les Précurseurs; les Chaires et les 6 Représentants; les Dépositaires d’une tradition; Riassunto; Images. La lecture nous permet de connaître bien des détails sur le fonctionnement des centres culturels roumains en Italie, sur l’activité de la presse roumaine, sur les actions initiées par les ministères roumains liés à la diplomatie culturelle — le Ministère de l’Éducation et de la Culture, celui des Affaires Étrangères, celui de la Propagande, sur l’activité des professeurs qui enseignaient le roumain en Italie. Tout cela dans un contexte historique dont les changements ont beaucoup influencé les relations italo-roumaines, dans le plan politique et culturel. Par exemple, l’auteur mentionne les discriminations raciales qui ont fait que des intellectuels roumains d’origine juive soient obligés par les autorités roumaines à rentrer en Roumanie et à quitter leur fonction ou le fait que ces professeurs, tellement dédiés à leur mission culturelle, attendaient du régime communiste une amélioration de leur situation. Mais ce régime a interrompu brusquement les relations avec l’Italie et a provoqué le refus de la plupart de ces intellectuels de rentrer en Roumanie. Le livre a le mérite de présenter d’une manière objective la diplomatie culturelle roumaine en Italie, et l’auteur met en lumière avec intelligence l’entrecroisement de la politique avec la culture. L’activité de ces intellectuels ne doit pas étre oubliée, elle peut offrir un modèle même aujourd’hui, dans le contexte où la Roumanie a besoin de se construire une image positive à l’étranger, favorable à l’intégration européenne, un enjeu politique qui pourrait se servir des instruments de la diplomatie culturelle. Ruxandra Luca THE REVIEW OF REVIEWS The Journal APPRAISAL, vol. 5 no. 3, March 2005 (Great Britain), edited by Richard T. Allen, is exploring an area of general interest in (political) contemporary philosophy, the post-critical and personalist studies. From the contents of this issue there are to be mentioned, amongst others, the actual study entitled A dialogic constitution of the person, by Tomas Taransky, On being responsible for acting irresponsibly, by Richard Prust and Benjamin Huff, but also Communal morality, by R.J. Brownhill. A second main aspect to highlight is the announcement of the 7th & 8th April SPCPS conference on post-critical and personalist studies organized with Nottingham University. From the pages of the journal the reader might notice, as well, the part dedicated to the scientific life, to recent seminars and conferences — the report on the 8th International Conference on Persons, Warsaw, August 9th–12th 2005, and, at the same time, the presentation of the Romanian conference with international participation (the American E. Gilder visiting professor at Sibiu University, the editor, R.T. Allen and the Chilean Cultural Attaché) occasioned by the 110th anniversary of the philosopher L. Blaga organized by “Revista de filosofie” in September 2005. The brief and substantial considerations of the editor might trigger an interest in Blaga’s philosophy. “They (E. Gilder and collab.) concluded: “Approaching the parallel between ironism (Rorty) and the historical being (Blaga) one understands that the tragedy of historical being is therefore counter-balanced, in a very complex and tensioned way, by chances to live authentically as a (liberal) ironist and as an inherently creative being’. But Blaga, I would add, also said that experience there is something more to, and corrective of, philosophy.” Henrieta ªerban REVISTA DE FILOSOFIE, no. 1-2/2005, edited by the Romanian Academy presents a first groupage on The history of the contemporary philosophyJacques Derrida (1930-2004) where the reader can find an interesting interview with K. McKenna, The Three Ages of Derrida, the study The Journey of Derrida from Socrates and Plato to Freud and Heidegger, by Angela Botez, Death at Nice – feeling thorn apart by Teodora Pavel and The Issue of logical and Mathematical Idealities in the ‘Phenomenological’ Lectures of Derrida, by Victor Botez. A special attention should be given to Petru Vaida’s concept of human genre in the philosophy of the last Lukács, and to the elements of modernity identified at Nichifor Crainic by Mona Mamulea, and, as well, to the signal concerning Professor Alexandru Boboc’s recent book Nietzsche between Elenism and Modernity, or Beyond Actual and Inactual. Henrieta ªerban REVISTA DE FILOSOFIE, no. 3-4/2005, edited by the Romanian Academy was dedicated to Blaga’s anniversary. Professor Alexandru Surdu, PhD, member of the Romanian Academy, tackles the actuality and potentiality of Blaga and Lupaºcu’s ideas. The diplomat and specialist on Kant Rainer Schubert investigates the production of a conscience of time at Blaga and Kant. Professor Mircea Flonta, PhD, explores the historicity and progress at Blaga, Professor Alexandru Boboc, PhD, member of the Romanian Academy Pol. Sc. Int. Rel., II, 2, p. 127–129, Bucharest, 2005. investigates the metaphor and the myth at Blaga and Cassirer, while Professor Angela Botez, director of “Revista de filosofie”, compares aspects like convergence and transcendentalism at Blaga and Emerson, while Aurel Codoban confronts ideas from Eliade and Blaga. The articles from the header Logics, argumentation and interpretation bring critical approaches of the paraconsistent logic, of the logic of accept and of the exercise of argumentation at Aristotle, J. St. Mill, B. Russell and Hintikka. Henrieta ªerban 128 THE REVIEW OF REVIEWS La revue STUDIA POLITICA, editée par l’Institut de Recherche Politique — centre de recherche qui fonctionne sous le patronage de l’Université de Bucarest — nous propose dans le numero 3/2005 un sommaire divers et de qualité, où l’on peut trouver comme un point de convergence l’intérêt pour l’analyse de la realite roumaine, à partir de diverses approches sur les divers secteurs de la vie sociale. La variété du sommaire compose un tableau intéressant de la société roumaine de différentes époques historiques. On va se concentrer sur les premiers trois articles qui, à la lumière du passé, construisent des messages instructifs pour le présent, surtout en ce qui concerne la modernisation, problème qui a préoccupé les hommes politiques roumains au XIXe siècle, lorsqu’il s’agissait de construire l’État moderne et de réaliser la synchronisation avec l’Europe Occidentale. La modernisation est liée à la construction politique de la nation roumaine, du libéralisme roumain à l’époque qui débute avec la moitié du XIXe siècle et de l’articulation des mécanismes démocratiques, où un rôle déterminant revenait au parlementarisme et à la participation politique. De ces trois articles on voit se contourer les questions fondamentales dans le discours sur la nation roumaine et sur sa construction politique, cela dans le contexte des relations politiques internationales: les auteurs paraissent s’interroger principalement sur le statut de l’État roumain dans ce contexte international, sur le rapport entre le centre et la périphérie dans le développement de la civilisation européenne et sur l’impacte de la position périphérique des pays roumains sur la modernisation de la société roumaine. Quel serait donc le bon équilibre entre le désir de garder la spécificité roumaine et le besoin de synchroniser la société au niveau de développement de l’Europe Occidentale? Où se trouve-t-il le mécanisme dont dépend la difficulté d’abandonner la résistance au changement — celui-ci toujours inspiré par des modèles occidentaux — en faveur de la modernisation? Comment faut-il faire ce changement, sans toucher aux particularités du fondement roumain, qui est fortement valorisé par les hommes de culture et les hommes politiques roumains qui critiquent les formes sans fond? De possibles réponses résultent des articles auxquels on fait référence dans cette sommaire présentation. Pour illustrer les préoccupations des auteurs on va citer de leurs textes. De la sorte, le prof. Daniel Barbu s’interroge: “Were the Romanian Liberals, like other political elites form the periphery of modern Europe just a `class of importers` facing the difficult assignement of adjusting a form of government and an ideal of political reform that they learned to admire elsewhere to a benighted and unyileding traditional society?”1. Et à cette question, l’auteur donne une réponse, qui est inscrite dans le même cadre expliquatif constitué par l’équation centre-périphérie: “It seems that in the European peripheral societies, where modernity was still 2 overdue and industrialization was late to visit the 19th century, the intellectual juxtaposition between form and foundation, illusion and reality, words and facts allowed for an artificial polarization of the political actors of the representative regime, between a ‘red’ liberal and progressive Left and a reactionary, conservative and traditional Right”2. Certainement, il n’est pas possible et d’ailleurs on ne s’est pas proposé par ces citations d’épuiser le contenu de l’article, dont la richesse argumentative résulte de l’analyse des faits historiques et des positions adoptées par les hommes politiques de cette époque qui marque le passage du XIXe au XXe siècle. Le titre de l’article — The Nation against Democracy. State Formation, Liberalism, and Political Participation in Romania — est d’ailleurs suggestif pour l’idée que l’auteur veut démontrer. L’article de Silvia Marton — dont le titre est Les libéraux roumains. Entre l’archéologie identitaire et la construction politique de la nation roumaine vers la moitié du XIXe siècle — est construit à partir de l’analyse de la manière où les libéraux articulaient leur doctrine sur des thèmes suggestifs dans l’ensemble de la construction politique roumaine (l’Union et la «nationalité»; comment peut-on devenir, du point de la loi, citoyen roumain; la nature de la représentation politique), dans le contexte historique du XIXe siècle. L’analyse porte sur l’activité et les discours des parlementaires, qui constituent une riche source pour reconstruire les débats de l’époque: «Les parlementaires roumains expriment d’une manière qui leur est propre un des paradoxes ‘troublants’ des États du Centre et du Sud-Est de l’Europe, concernant la combinaison entre l’archaïque et la modernité. On proclame la nécessité de la modernisation rapide — les députés prennent toujours comme modèle «l’Europe civilisée» — et on invoque en même temps la tradition des «ancêtres», tout comme la durée considérable de l’État, tradition et continuité étatique qui, dans la voie de la modernisation, doivent piloter les actes du nouvel État»3. Silvia Marton lie la «conduite» des parlementaires roumains au cadre de l’idéologie libérale de la moitié du XIXe siècle, à savoir à une certaine hiérarchie des nations, qui faisait de leur progrès, de leur civilisation, de leur grandeur, une précondition de l’État-nation. Les critères qui permettaient à un peuple de se considérer une nation et qui construisaient cette hiérarchie sont ceux établis par E. Hobsbawm et invoqués par Silvia Marton4 (l’existence d’un État actuel ou d’une mémoire historique et d’une tradition; l’existence des élites culturelles de longue tradition et ayant cultivé une langue écrite; la capacité de conquérir de nouveaux territoires) pour appliquer ce modèle au cas des libéraux roumains. Les conclusions sont bien intéressantes. L’article signé par Raluca Alexandrescu sous le titre La démocratie roumaine: vocation ou exercice de volonté, traite à son tour de la modernité politique roumaine de la seconde moitié du XIXe siècle, 3 THE REVIEW OF REVIEWS de la perspective de l’histoire conceptuelle, à partir des directions concurrentes qui existaient à cette époque entre les intellectuels et les hommes politiques impliqués dans ces débats: les libéraux et les conservateurs. R. Alexandrescu propose une nouvelle approche méthodologique pour opérer avec les concepts que l’on utilise dans les discours sur la démocratie. Dans le sommaire de la revue on trouve d’autres études sur: les réseaux franco-hongrois et la France, de 1896 à 1914 (Nicolas Bauquet), le conflit générationnel et politique dans le milieu des écrivains bessarabiens de l’entre-deux-guerres (Petru Negurã), le mouvement des femmes roumaines entre 1929–1944 129 (Alexandra Petrescu), la propagande communiste au département de Ialomiþa (Rãzvan Pantelimon), la philosophie marxiste dans la Roumanie communiste (Alexandru Stãiculescu), Vladimir Tismãneanu — historien du communisme roumain (Dragoº Petrescu, Cristina Petrescu), la coopération, la confiance et les préjugés ethniques en Roumanie (Dragoº Dragoman). La rubrique Annales nous propose une lecture chronologique de la vie politique roumaine actuelle, pour la période 1 avril–30 juin 2005. La revue nous offre une série de récensions des livres actuels, et une présentation des auteurs ayant contribué au présent numéro, très utile pour connaître leur profil intellectuel et professionnel. NOTES 1. Daniel Barbu, The Nation against Democracy. State Formation, Liberalism, and Political Participation in Romania, en: “Studia Politica”, vol. V, no. 3/2005, p. 550. 2. Ibidem, p. 551. 3. Silvia Marton, Liberalii români. Între arheologia identitarã ºi construcþia politicã a naþiunii la jumãtatea secolului al XIX-lea, en: “Studia politica”, vol. V, no. 3/2005, pp. 568–569. 4. Ibidem, pp. 566–567. Ruxandra Luca INTERNATIONAL POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW: Editor Kay Lawson, San Francisco State University; Dr. James, Meadowcroft School of Public Policy and Administration Carleton University. The International Political Science Review is the quarterly journal of the International Political Science Association. It seeks to meet the needs of political scientists throughout the world who are interested in studying political phenomena in the contemporary context of increasing international interdependence and global change. The Review is committed to publishing material that makes a significant contribution to international political science. IPSR reflects the aims and intellectual tradition of the International Political Science Association: to foster the creation and dissemination of rigorous political inquiry free of subdisciplinary or other orthodoxy. It welcomes work by scholars who are focusing on currently controversial themes, shaping innovative concepts and methodologies of political analysis, and striving to reach outside the scope of a single culture. “The International Political Science Review is one of the few journals that has a truly international authorship. Its theme issues often explore new territory outside mainstream political science, thereby invigorating theoretical and methodological debate and renewal. It is an indispensable source of knowledge and insight for the well-rounded social scientist”(Kalevi J. Holsti). Submissions should be made electronically to the two General Editors at the email addresses: [email protected]; [email protected]. The author’s name, title, affiliation and full contact details should be given on a separate page as articles are subjected to anonymous peer review before being accepted for publication. Submissions should normally be no longer than 10,000 words including references and notes and should be double spaced throughout. Notes, references, tables and charts should be placed as separate pages and follow the current journal style. A 100 words abstract should be included with each submission. International Political Science Review is available also electronically on SAGE Journals Online at http://ipsr.sagepub.com. Lucian Jora